Research article

Acyclic edge coloring of planar graphs

  • Received: 08 December 2021 Revised: 04 March 2022 Accepted: 07 March 2022 Published: 31 March 2022
  • MSC : 05C10, 05C15

  • An acyclic edge coloring of a graph G is a proper edge coloring such that no bichromatic cycles are produced. The acyclic chromatic index of G, denoted by χa(G), is the smallest integer k such that G is acyclically edge k-colorable. In this paper, we consider the planar graphs without 3-cycles and intersecting 4-cycles, and prove that χa(G)Δ(G)+1 if Δ(G)8.

    Citation: Yuehua Bu, Qi Jia, Hongguo Zhu, Junlei Zhu. Acyclic edge coloring of planar graphs[J]. AIMS Mathematics, 2022, 7(6): 10828-10841. doi: 10.3934/math.2022605

    Related Papers:

    [1] Fugang Chao, Donghan Zhang . Neighbor sum distinguishing total choice number of IC-planar graphs with restrictive conditions. AIMS Mathematics, 2023, 8(6): 13637-13646. doi: 10.3934/math.2023692
    [2] Hongyu Chen, Li Zhang . A smaller upper bound for the list injective chromatic number of planar graphs. AIMS Mathematics, 2025, 10(1): 289-310. doi: 10.3934/math.2025014
    [3] Jin Cai, Shuangliang Tian, Lizhen Peng . On star and acyclic coloring of generalized lexicographic product of graphs. AIMS Mathematics, 2022, 7(8): 14270-14281. doi: 10.3934/math.2022786
    [4] Xiaoxue Hu, Jiangxu Kong . An improved upper bound for the dynamic list coloring of 1-planar graphs. AIMS Mathematics, 2022, 7(5): 7337-7348. doi: 10.3934/math.2022409
    [5] Yunfeng Tang, Huixin Yin, Miaomiao Han . Star edge coloring of $ K_{2, t} $-free planar graphs. AIMS Mathematics, 2023, 8(6): 13154-13161. doi: 10.3934/math.2023664
    [6] Yueying Zhao, Lianying Miao . Planar graphs without $ \{4, 6, 8\} $-cycles are 3-choosable. AIMS Mathematics, 2021, 6(9): 10253-10265. doi: 10.3934/math.2021593
    [7] Yuehua Bu, Qiang Yang, Junlei Zhu, Hongguo Zhu . Injective coloring of planar graphs with girth 5. AIMS Mathematics, 2023, 8(7): 17081-17090. doi: 10.3934/math.2023872
    [8] Yanyi Li, Lily Chen . Injective edge coloring of generalized Petersen graphs. AIMS Mathematics, 2021, 6(8): 7929-7943. doi: 10.3934/math.2021460
    [9] Yanping Yang, Yang Wang, Juan Liu . List vertex arboricity of planar graphs without 5-cycles intersecting with 6-cycles. AIMS Mathematics, 2021, 6(9): 9757-9769. doi: 10.3934/math.2021567
    [10] Ningge Huang, Lily Chen . AVD edge-colorings of cubic Halin graphs. AIMS Mathematics, 2023, 8(11): 27820-27839. doi: 10.3934/math.20231423
  • An acyclic edge coloring of a graph G is a proper edge coloring such that no bichromatic cycles are produced. The acyclic chromatic index of G, denoted by χa(G), is the smallest integer k such that G is acyclically edge k-colorable. In this paper, we consider the planar graphs without 3-cycles and intersecting 4-cycles, and prove that χa(G)Δ(G)+1 if Δ(G)8.



    All graphs considered in this paper are finite simple graphs. For a graph G, we use V(G), E(G), F(G), Δ(G) (Δ for short and reserved), and g(G) to denote the vertex set, edge set, face set, maximum degree and girth, respectively. A graph G is 2-connected if there are two paths between any two distinct vertices.

    Let G be a planar graph. The acyclic edge k-coloring of graph G is a mapping c:E(G){1,2,,k} such that any two adjacent edges receive different colors, and there are no bichromatic cycles in G. The acyclic chromatic index of G, denoted by χa(G), is the smallest integer k such that G is acyclically edge k-colorable.

    Fiamˇcik posed a famous conjecture for acyclic edge coloring of any graphs.

    Conjecture 1.1. [3] For any graph G, χa(G)Δ(G)+2.

    The conjecture is still open.

    For any graph G, Alon, McDiarmid and Reed [1] proved that χa(G)64Δ. Molloy and Reed [8] improved this bound to 16Δ. Later, Fialho et al. [4] showed that χa(G)3.569(Δ1), and most recently to 2Δ1 by Kirousis and Livieratos [7].

    There have been numerous investigations about acyclic edge coloring of planar graphs.

    For any planar graph G, Basavaraju et al. [2] proved that χa(G)Δ+12, Wang et al. [9] proved that χa(G)Δ+7, Wang and Zhang [10] proved that χa(G)Δ+6.

    Let G be a planar graph with small grith. Shu, Wang and Wang [11] proved that χa(G)Δ(G)+2 if g(G)4. For planar graph G with g(G)5, Hou et al.[6] proved that χa(G)Δ(G)+1; they also proved that such graph has χa(G)=Δ(G) if Δ(G)9. For planar graph G without 4-cycles, Wang and Sheng [13] proved that χa(G)Δ(G)+3. Then Wang, Shu and Wang [14] improved this bound to Δ(G)+2 when Δ(G)5. In 2012, Fiedorowicz [5] proved that the planar graph G without an i-cycle intersect to a j-cycle has χa(G)Δ(G)+2 for i,j{3,4}. Most recently, Shu et al. [12] proved that the planar graph G without intersecting triangles has χa(G)Δ(G)+2.

    In this paper, we consider the planar graph without 3-cycles and intersecting 4-cycles, and prove the following theorem:

    Theorem 1.1. Let G be a planar graph without 3-cycles and intersecting 4-cycles. If Δ(G)8, then χa(G)Δ(G)+1.

    Let G be a simple planar graph. For a vertex vV(G), N(v) denotes the set of vertices adjacent to v, and d(v)=|N(v)| denotes the degree of v. For fF(G), we use b(f) to denote the boundary walk of f and write f=[u1u2un] if u1,u2,,un are the vertices on b(f) enumerated in the clockwise direction. For f=[u1u2un], let δ(f) denote the minimum degree of any vertex on b(f). That is, δ(f)=min{d(ui),i=1,,n}. The degree of a face f, denoted by d(f), is the number of edges in its boundary walk.

    For fF(G), f is called a k-(or k+-, or k-) face if d(f)=k (or d(f)k, or d(f)k). For vV(G), v is called a k-(or k+-, or k-) vertex if d(v)=k (or d(v)k, or d(v)k). If uN(v) and d(u)=k, then u is called k-neighbor of v. Let Nk(v)={xN(v)|d(x)=k}, and nk(v)=|Nk(v)|.

    Let c be an edge coloring of G and v be a vertex of G. Then, C(v)={c(uv):uN(v)}, Fcv(uv)=C(v){c(uv)}. Let α,β be two colors. An (α,β)-bichromatic path with respect to c is a path consisting of edges that are colored with α and β alternately. An (α,β)-bichromatic path which starts at the vertex u via an edge colored α and ends at v via an edge colored α is an (α,β)(u,v)-bichromatic path. We use "w.l.o.g." as a shorthand for "without loss of generality".

    We apply a discharging procedure to prove Theorem 1.1. Discharging is a tool in a two-pronged approach to inductive proofs. It can be viewed as an amortized counting argument used to prove that a global hypothesis guarantees the existence of some desirable local configurations. In an application of the resulting structure theorem, one shows that each such local configuration cannot occur in a minimal counterexample to the desired conclusion. Such local configurations are called reducible configurations. In this section, we give some reducible configurations.

    Let G be a counterexample with minimum |V(G)|+|E(G)| of Theorem 1.1. In other words, G is a connected simple planar graph without 3-cycles and intersecting 4-cycles, Δ=Δ(G)8, but χa(G)Δ+2. Let C be a color set of G, C={1,2,,Δ+1}. Now, we discuss the structures of G.

    Lemma 3.1. The graph G is 2-connected.

    Proof. By contradiction, suppose that v is a cut vertex of G. Let C1,C2,,Ct(t2) be the connected components of Gv. For each 1it, there is an acyclic (Δ+1)-edge coloring ci of Gi=Ci{v}. We can adjust the colors in each ci such that the colors appearing on the edges incident with v are all distinct. Now the union of these colorings is an acyclic (Δ+1)-edge coloring of G, a contradiction.

    Lemma 3.2. The graph G does not contain a 2-vertex adjacent to a 3-vertex.

    Proof. By contradiction, let d(v)=2,N(v)={u,w}, d(u)3 (See Figure 1(1)). We prove the case d(u)=3, and d(u)=2 can be proved in a similar way. Let N(u)={v,u1,u2}, G=Guv. By the minimality of G, G admits an acyclic (Δ+1)-edge coloring c. Suppose that c(uui)=i for i=1,2.

    We consider the following two cases.

    Figure 1.  The configurations of Lemmas 3.2 and 3.4.

    Case 3.1. |C(u)C(v)|=0.

    Since |C(C(u)C(v))|=Δ+13=Δ2>0, we can color uv with α for αC(C(u)C(v)). Therefore, c can be extended to be an acyclic (Δ+1)-edge coloring of G, a contradiction.

    Case 3.2. |C(u)C(v)|=1.W.l.o.g., assume that c(vw)=c(uu1)=1. If there exists a color γ{3,,Δ+1} such that G contains no (1,γ)(u,v)-bichromatic path via u1 and w, then we can color uv with γ. In this way G is acyclically edge (Δ+1)-colorable, a contradiction. Thus, there must exist a (1,α)(u,v)-bichromatic path via u1 and w for each α{3,4,,Δ+1}. So C(u1)=C(w)={1,3,4,,Δ+1}. Now we recolor vw with 2. Similarly, there must exist a (2,α)(u,v)-bichromatic path via u2 and w for each α{3,4,,Δ+1}. So C(u2)={2,3,4,,Δ+1}. Now we exchange the colors between uu1 and uu2, color uv with 3, color vw with 1. Therefore, c can be extended to be an acyclic (Δ+1)-edge coloring of G, a contradiction.

    Next we discuss the degree sum of the neighbors of a particular vertex.

    Lemma 3.3. Let d(v)=k{2,3} and N(v)={vi,1ik}. Then ki=1d(vi)Δ+k+1.

    Proof. By contradiction, assume that ki=1d(vi)Δ+k. Let G=Gvv1, by the minimality of G, G admits an acyclic (Δ+1)-edge coloring c. Since the neighbors of each 2-vertex are both 4+-vertices, we have 3d(vi)Δ+k6 when 1i3 and k=3. Suppose that c(vvi)=i1 for i=2,,k. We consider the following three cases.

    Case 3.3. |C(v1)C(v)|=0.

    Since |C(C(v1)C(v))|=Δ+1(d(v1)1)(d(v)1)=Δ+3d(v1)d(v)Δd(v1)>0, we can color vv1 with α for αC(C(v1)C(v)). Therefore, c can be extended to be an acyclic (Δ+1)-edge coloring of G, a contradiction.

    Case 3.4. |C(v1)C(v)|=1. W.l.o.g., assume that 1C(v1).

    (i) k=2.

    Since |C(C(v1)C(v2))|Δ+1(d(v1)1)(d(v2)1)=Δ+3(d(v1)+d(v2))Δ+3(Δ+2)=1, we can color vv1 with β for βC(C(v1)C(v2)).Therefore, c can be extended to be an acyclic (Δ+1)-edge coloring of G, a contradiction.

    (ii) k=3.

    Since |C(C(v1)C(v)C(v2))|Δ+1(d(v1)1)1(d(v2)1)=Δ(d(v1)+d(v2))+2ΔΔ+2=2, we can color vv1 with α for αC(C(v1)C(v)C(v2)), c is an acyclic (Δ+1)-edge coloring of G, a contradiction.

    Case 3.5. |C(v1)C(v)|=2. Namely, d(v)=k=3.

    Since |C(C(v1)C(v2)C(v3))|Δ+1(d(v1)1)(d(v2)1)(d(v3)1)=Δ(d(v1)+d(v2)+d(v3))+41, we can color vv1 with α for αC(C(v1)C(v2)C(v3)), c is an acyclic (Δ+1)-edge coloring of G, a contradiction.

    For a 2-vertex, the number of 3-vertex and Δ-vertex of its neighbors is discussed below.

    Lemma 3.4. For a 2-vertex v, let N(v)={x,y}. Then (1) n2(x)d(x)+d(y)Δ2; (2) n2(x)+n3(x)d(x)+d(y)Δ1; (3) n2(x)+n3(x)d(x)+d(y)Δ2 if d(x)<Δ.

    Proof. Assume that d(x)=s+1,d(y)=t+1,N(x)={v,x1,x2,,xs},N(y)={v,y1,y2,,yt} (See Figure 1(2)). Let G=Gvy, G admits an acyclic (Δ+1)-edge coloring c. Let c(yyi)=i for 1it,T=CFcx(vx). It is clear that |T|=Δ+1s2.

    If TFcy(vy), then we can recolor vx with α for αTFcy(vy), color vy with β for β{t+1,,Δ+1}(βα). Now c can be extended to be an acyclic (Δ+1)-edge coloring of G, a contradiction. So TFcy(vy)={1,2,,t}.

    If there are i0T and j0{t+1,,Δ+1}, such that G contains no (i0,j0)(v,y)-bichromatic path through x, then we can color vx with i0, color vy with j0, G is acyclically edge (Δ+1)-colorable, a contradiction. So G contains (α0,j)(v,y)-bichromatic path for c(vx)=α0,α0T and j{t+1,,Δ+1}. This means that {t+1,,Δ+1}Fcx(vx). W.l.o.g., let c(xxi)=t+i for 1iΔ+1t. Now recolor c(vx)=i for any iT. Similarly, G contains (i,j)(v,y)-bichromatic path for any j{t+1,,Δ+1}. So TFcxl(xxl), which means that d(xl)|T|+1 for 1lΔ+1t.

    (1) Since d(x)Δ, |T|=Δ+1s=Δ+1(d(x)1)=Δd(x)+22. This means that d(xi)3 for 1iΔ+1t. Therefore, n2(x)d(x)(Δ+1t)=d(x)Δ1+d(y)1=d(x)+d(y)Δ2.

    (2) If there are at least two 3-vertices in {x1,,xΔ+1t}, then assume that d(x1)=d(x2)=3. Since TFcxl(xxl)(1lΔ+1t), and d(x1)=d(x2)=3, we have T={1,2}. So Fcx1(xx1)=Fcx2(xx2)={1,2}. Now we exchange the colors between xx1 and xx2, color vx with 1, color vy with t+1, G is acyclically edge (Δ+1)-colorable, a contradiction. Therefore, n2(x)+n3(x)d(x)(Δ+1t)+1=d(x)+d(y)Δ1.

    (3) If d(x)<Δ, then |T|=Δ+1s=Δ+1(d(x)1)=Δd(x)+23. This implies that d(xl)|T|+14 for 1lΔ+1t. Therefore, n2(x)+n3(x)d(x)(Δ+1t)=d(x)Δ1+d(y)1=d(x)+d(y)Δ2.

    Lemma 3.5. For 2-vertex v, let N(v)={x,y}. If n2(x)=d(x)2, then nΔ(x)=2, n2(y)=1, n3(y)1, d(y)=Δ.

    Proof. Let N(x)={v,x1,x2,,xs},N(y)={v,y1,y2,,yt}, d(xi)=2, N(xi)={x,xi} for 3is (See Figure 2(3)). Observe that n2(x)d(x)+d(y)Δ2 by Lemma 3.4. If n2(x)=d(x)2, then d(y)=Δ, which means that t=Δ1. Let G=Gxv, G admits an acyclic (Δ+1)-edge coloring c. Suppose that c(xxi)=i for 1is,T=CFcy(vy). It is clear that |T|=Δ+1(d(y)1)=2.

    Figure 2.  The configurations of Lemmas 3.5 and 3.6.

    (1) nΔ(x)=2,n2(y)=1.

    We consider the following two cases.

    Case 3.6. TFcx(vx).

    We can recolor vy with α for αTFcx(vx), color vx with β for β{s+1,,Δ+1}(βα). Now c can be extended to be an acyclic (Δ+1)-edge coloring of G, a contradiction.

    Case 3.7. TFcx(vx)=.

    That is, TFcx(vx)={1,2,,s}.

    (i) T{3,,s}.

    Let αT{3,,s}. Since |C(C(x)C(xα))|Δ+1(d(x)1)1=Δ+1d(x)1, we can color vy with α, color vx with β for βC(C(x)C(xα)), c can be extended to be an acyclic (Δ+1)-edge coloring of G, a contradiction.

    (ii) T{3,,s}=.

    That is, T = {1,2} and Fcy(vy) = {3,4,,Δ+1}. Note that c(vy){1,2}, w.l.o.g., suppose that c(vy) = 1. If there is a color γ{s+1,,Δ+1} such that G contains no (1,γ)(x,v)-bichromatic path via x1 and y, then we can color vx with γ. In this way G is acyclically edge (Δ+1)-colorable, a contradiction. So there must exist a (1,j)(x,v)-bichromatic path via x1 and y for each j(j{s+1,,Δ+1}), which implies that {s+1,,Δ+1}C(x1)C(y). Now we recolor vy with 2, and don't change the colors of the other edges, c is still an acyclic (Δ+1)-edge coloring of Gxv. As the same argument above, we have that {s+1,,Δ+1}C(x2). If there is i{3,4,,s}, such that G contains no (1,i)(x,v)-bichromatic path via x1 and y, then we can color vx with i. Don't change the colors of the other edges, and remove the color of xxi, c is still an acyclic (Δ+1)-edge coloring of Gxxi, now we consider the color of xxi. W.l.o.g., assume that i=3.

    If c(x3x3)=js+1, then |C(x)C(x3)|s+1=d(x)Δ, we can color xx3 with α for α(C(x)C(x3)), G is acyclically edge (Δ+1)-colorable, a contradiction.

    If c(x3x3)=j{1,2}, then it can be seen from the above argument that for each α{s+1,,Δ+1}, there are (i,α)(x,v)-bichromatic paths (i=1,2). So Gxx3 contains no (i,α)(x,x3)-bichromatic path (i=1,2) for each α{s+1,,Δ+1}, we can color xx3 with α, G is acyclically edge (Δ+1)-colorable, a contradiction.

    If c(x3x3)=j=3, then we can color xx3 with α for α(C(x)C(v)) since |C(x)C(v)|s+1=d(x)<Δ+1, G is acyclically edge (Δ+1)-colorable, a contradiction.

    If c(x3x3)=j{4,,s}, then we can recolor xx3 with α for α(C(x)C(xj)) since |C(x)C(xj)|s+1=d(x)<Δ+1, G is acyclically edge (Δ+1)-colorable, a contradiction. Hence, there are (1,i)(x,v)-bichromatic paths via x1 and y for each i{3,4,,s}, which implies that {1,3,4,,s}C(x1).

    In conclusion, C(x1)=C(y)={1,3,4,,Δ+1}. Now recolor vy with 2, and don't change the colors of the other edges, c is still an acyclic (Δ+1)-edge coloring of Gxv. As the same argument above, we have that C(x2)={2,3,4,,Δ+1}. It follows that Fcx1(xx1)=Fcx2(xx2)=Fcy(vy)={3,4,,Δ+1} and {1,2}Fcyi(yyi) for 1it. Then d(x1)=d(x2)=Δ+12+1=Δ,n2(y)=1.

    (2) n3(y)1.

    By contradiction, assume that d(y1)=d(y2)=3. Now exchange the colors between yy1 and yy2, and don't change the colors of the other edges, Gxv has a new acyclic (Δ+1)-edge coloring ϕ. Let ϕ(yy1)=α.

    If α{s+1,,Δ+1}, then let ϕ(xv)=α. By symmetry, suppose that ϕ(vy)=1, G is acyclically edge (Δ+1)-colorable, a contradiction.

    If α{3,4,,s}, assume that α=3, then let ϕ(xv)=3, remove the color of xx3, Gxx3 admits an acyclic (Δ+1)-edge coloring ϕ. Let ϕ(x3x3)=β. It follows from the above argument that there is a (1,Δ)(x,v)-bichromatic path through x1, so Gxx3 contains no (1,Δ)(x,x3)-bichromatic path via x1 and x3. Similarly, Gxx3 contains no (2,Δ)(x,x3)-bichromatic path via x2 and x3. If β{1,2}, then let ϕ(xx3)=Δ, G is acyclically edge (Δ+1)-colorable, a contradiction. If β{4,,s}, then let ϕ(xx3)=γ for γ(ϕ(x)ϕ(xβ)), G is acyclically edge (Δ+1)-colorable, a contradiction. If βs+1, then let ϕ(xx3)=γ for γ(ϕ(x)ϕ(x3)), G is acyclically edge (Δ+1)-colorable, a contradiction. This implies that n3(y)1.

    Lemma 3.6. For 2-vertex v, let N(v)={x,y}. If d(x)=4 and n2(x)+n3(x)=2, then nΔ(x)=2, n2(y)=1,n3(y)1,d(y)=Δ.

    Proof. Note that n2(x)+n3(x)d(x)+d(y)Δ2=d(y)Δ+2 by Lemma 3.4. It is clear that d(y)=Δ since n2(x)+n3(x)=2. Let N(x)={v,x1,x2,x3},N(y)={v,y1,y2,,yΔ1} (See Figure 2(4)). If n2(x)=d(x)2=2, then nΔ(x)=2,n2(y)=1 and n3(y)1 by Lemma 3.5. We prove the case n2(x)=1 and n3(x)=1. Suppose that d(x3)=3. Let G=Gxv, by the minimality of G, G admits an acyclic (Δ+1)-edge coloring c. Assume that c(xxi)=i for 1i3, T=CFcy(vy). Clearly, |T|=Δ+1(Δ1)=2.

    (1) nΔ(x)=2,n2(y)=1.

    We consider the following two cases.

    Case 3.8. TFcx(vx).

    We can recolor vy with α for αTFcx(vx), color vx with β for β{4,,Δ+1}(βα), c is an acyclic (Δ+1)-edge coloring of G, a contradiction.

    Case 3.9. TFcx(vx)=.

    That is, TFcx(vx)={1,2,3}. Since |T|=Δ+1(Δ1)=2, {1,2,3}T. As the same argument of Case 2 in Lemma 3.5, we have nΔ(x)=2,n2(y)=1 by setting s=3.

    (2) n3(y)1.

    By contradiction, suppose that d(y1)=d(y2)=3. It follows from the above argument that Fcy1(yy1)=Fcy2(yy2)={1,2}. By the symmetry, assume that c(vy)=1, exchange the colors between yy1 and yy2, Gxv has a new acyclic (Δ+1)-edge coloring ϕ. Let ϕ(yy1)=α.

    If α{4,,Δ+1}, then let ϕ(vx)=α, G is acyclically edge (Δ+1)-colorable, a contradiction.

    If α=3, then let ϕ(xv)=3, and remove the color of xx3, Gxx3 has an acyclic (Δ+1)-edge coloring ϕ. It follows from the above argument that there are (i,γ)(x,v)-bichromatic paths under c of Gxv for i=1,2 and γ{4,5,,Δ+1}. So Gxx3 contains no (i,γ)(x,x3)-bichromatic path. If |ϕ(x)ϕ(x3)|=0, then |ϕ(x)ϕ(x3)|3+2=5<Δ+1. Let ϕ(xx3)=β for βC(ϕ(x)ϕ(x3)), ϕ can be extended to G, a contradiction. If |ϕ(x)ϕ(x3)|=1, then suppose 1ϕ(x3). Let ϕ(xx3)=β for β{4,,Δ+1}ϕ(x3), ϕ can be extended to G, a contradiction. If |ϕ(x)ϕ(x3)|=2, then ϕ(x)ϕ(x3)={1,2}, we can let ϕ(xx3)=β for β{4,,Δ+1}, ϕ can be extended to G, a contradiction. This implies that n3(y)1.

    Next we discuss the number of 3-vertex in the neighbors of Δ-vertex.

    Lemma 3.7. For d(v)=Δ, if n2(v)Δ3, then n2(v)+n3(v)Δ2.

    Proof. Assume that v4N(v), N(v4)={v,v4}. By Lemma 3.4, n2(v)d(v)+d(v4)Δ2=d(v4)2Δ2, n2(v)+n3(v)d(v)+d(v4)Δ1=d(v4)1Δ1; if n2(v)=Δ2, then d(v4)=Δ; if n2(v)+n3(v)=Δ1, then d(v4)=Δ. Note that nΔ(v)=2 when n2(v)=Δ2 by Lemma 3.5. Namely n3(v)=0, n2(v)+n3(v)=Δ2+0=Δ2.

    Otherwise n2(v)=Δ3. By contradiction, suppose that n2(v)+n3(v)Δ1. We have that n2(v)+n3(v)=Δ1 since n2(v)+n3(v)Δ1. Let N(v)={v1,v2,,vΔ},N(vi)={v,xi} for 4iΔ. Assume that d(v2)=d(v3)=3 (See Figure 3(5)). Let G=GvvΔ, by the minimality of G, G admits an acyclic (Δ+1)-edge coloring c. Let c(vvi)=i for 1iΔ1,T=CFcxΔ(vΔxΔ). Since n2(v)+n3(v)=Δ1, it follows from the above argument that d(xΔ)=d(xΔ1)==d(x4)=Δ, |T|=Δ+1(Δ1)=2.

    We consider the following two cases.

    Figure 3.  The configurations of Lemmas 3.7 and 3.8.

    Case 3.10. TC(v).

    We can recolor vΔxΔ with α for αTC(v), color vvΔ with β for β{Δ,Δ+1}(βα), c is an acyclic (Δ+1)-edge coloring of G, a contradiction.

    Case 3.11. TC(v)=. That is, TC(v)={1,2,,Δ1}.

    (i) T{4,5,,Δ1}.

    We can color vΔxΔ with i for iT{4,5,,Δ1}, color vvΔ with j for j{Δ,Δ+1}{c(vixi)}, G is acyclically edge (Δ+1)-colorable, a contradiction.

    (ii) T{4,5,,Δ1}=.

    That is, T{1,2,3}. Note that c(vΔxΔ)T{1,2,3}. When c(vΔxΔ)=1, if there exists a color γ{Δ,Δ+1}, such that G contains no (1,γ)(v,vΔ)-bichromatic path via xΔ and v1, then let c(vvΔ)=γ, G is acyclically edge (Δ+1)-colorable, a contradiction. Hence, G contains (1,i)(v,vΔ)-bichromatic paths via xΔ and v1 for each i{Δ,Δ+1}. This implies that {Δ,Δ+1}C(v1)C(xΔ). If 2T, then we can recolor vΔxΔ with 2, c is still an acyclic (Δ+1)-edge coloring of GvvΔ, the same argument shows that C(v2)={2,Δ,Δ+1}. If 3T, then we can recolor vΔxΔ with 3, c is still an acyclic (Δ+1)-edge coloring of GvvΔ, the same argument shows that C(v3)={3,Δ,Δ+1}.

    (a) 1T. Namely, T={2,3}.

    It follows from the above argument that Fcv2(vv2)=Fcv3(vv3)={Δ,Δ+1}. Now exchange the colors between vv2 and vv3, we can color vΔxΔ with α for αT, color vvΔ with Δ, G is acyclically edge (Δ+1)-colorable, a contradiction.

    (b) 1T. Suppose that T={1,2}.

    It follows from the above argument that {Δ,Δ+1}C(v1) and Fcv2(vv2)={Δ,Δ+1}. Now let c(vΔxΔ)=2,c(vvΔ)=7, remove the color of vv7, c is still an acyclic (Δ+1)-edge coloring of Gvv7. Let T=CFcx7(v7x7), it is clear that |T|=Δ+1(Δ1)=2. It follows from the above argument that T{1,2,3}, and 1T. Assume that c(v7x7)=1. Since there is a (1,Δ)(v,vΔ)-bichromatic path through v1, Gvv7 contains no (1,Δ)(v,v7)-bichromatic path via v1 and x7, we can color vv7 with Δ, G is acyclically edge (Δ+1)-colorable, a contradiction.

    The following Lemma shows if a k-vertex(k{4,5,6}) has no 2-neighbor, then n3(v)<k.

    Lemma 3.8. Let v be a k-vertex, with k{4,5,6}. If n2(v)=0, then n3(v)<k.

    Proof. By contradiction, suppose that n3(v)=k. Let N(v)={x,v1,v2,v3,v4,vk1},N(x)={v,x1,x2} and N(vi)={v,vi,vi}(1ik1) (See Figure 3(8)). Let G=Gxv, by the minimality of G, G admits an acyclic (Δ+1)-edge coloring c. Let c(vvi)=i for 1ik1. We consider the following three cases.

    Case 3.12. |C(x)C(v)|=0.

    Note that |C(C(x)C(v))|=Δ+12(k1)=Δk>0, we can color xv with α for αC(C(x)C(v)), c is an acyclic (Δ+1)-edge coloring of G, a contradiction.

    Case 3.13. |C(x)C(v)|=1.

    W.l.o.g., assume that c(xx1)=c(vv1)=1,c(xx2)=k. If there exists a color γ{k+1,,Δ+1} such that G contains no (1,γ)(x,v)-bichromatic path, then we can color xv with γ. In this way G is acyclically edge (Δ+1)-colorable, a contradiction. So there must exist (1,α)(x,v)-bichromatic paths for each α{k+1,,Δ+1}, which implies that {k+1,,Δ+1}C(x1)C(v1). Thus, d(v1)Δ+1k+1Δ44, a contradiction.

    Case 3.14. |C(x)C(v)|=2.

    W.l.o.g., assume that c(xx1)=c(vv1)=1,c(xx2)=c(vv2)=2.

    (i) Δ9.

    Since d(v1)=d(v2)=3 and Δ9, we have that {k,,Δ+1}(C(v1)C(v2)). Let β{k,,Δ+1}(C(v1)C(v2)). Note that G contains no (i,β)(x,v)-bichromatic path for i=1,2, we can color xv with β, c is an acyclic (Δ+1)-edge coloring of G, a contradiction.

    (ii) Δ=8.

    (a) k{4,5}.

    Since d(v1)=d(v2)=3 and Δ8, we have that {k,,Δ+1}(C(v1)C(v2)). Let β{k,,Δ+1}(C(v1)C(v2)). Note that G contains no (i,β)(x,v)-bichromatic path for i=1,2, we can color xv with β. In this way c is an acyclic (Δ+1)-edge coloring of G, a contradiction.

    (b) k=6.

    If there exists a color γ{6,7,8,9} such that G contains no (i,γ)(x,v)-bichromatic path for i=1,2, then we can color xv with γ. In this way G is acyclically edge (Δ+1)-colorable, a contradiction. So {6,7,8,9}(C(v1)C(v2)). Since d(v1)=d(v2)=3, we have that C(v1)C(v2)={1,2,6,7,8,9} and c(v1v1)C(v2),c(v1v1)C(v2). We can recolor vv2 with α for α{c(v1v1),c(v1v1)}, don't change the colors of the other edges, G has a new acyclic (Δ+1)-edge coloring c, and |C(x)C(v)|=1. By the similar argument in case 2, we can get an acyclic (Δ+1)-edge coloring of G, a contradiction.

    Note that G is a minimal counterexample to Theorem 1.1, and G is a connected planar graph. By Euler,s formula |V|+|F||E|=2 and the relation vV(G)d(v)=fF(G)d(f)=2|E(G)|, we can derive the identity

    vV(G)(d(v)4)+fF(G)(d(f)4)=8.

    We define the initial charge function by ω(v)=d(v)4 for vV(G) and ω(f)=d(f)4 for fF(G). It follows from the identity that xV(G)F(G)ω(x)=8. According to the structures of G, we design some discharging rules and redistribute charge such that the total amount of charge has not changed. Once the discharging is finished, a new charge function ω(x) is produced. Next, we prove ω(x)0 for all xV(G)F(G). Therefore, we can get the following contradiction

    0xV(G)F(G)ω(x)=xV(G)F(G)ω(x)=8.

    Hence, we demonstrate that the counterexample can not exist and Theorem 1.1 is proved.

    Discharging rules:

    (R1) Every 5+-face f sends d(f)4d(f) to each incident vertex.

    (R2) Every 4-vertex v sends 15 to each adjacent 3-vertex, and then distributes the remaining extra charge evenly among all adjacent 2-vertices.

    (R3) Every 5-vertex v sends 25 to each adjacent 3-vertex, and then distributes the remaining extra charge evenly among all adjacent 2-vertices.

    (R4) Every 6+-vertex v sends 35 to each adjacent 3-vertex, and then distributes the remaining extra charge evenly among all adjacent 2-vertices.

    In the following, we will prove that ω(v)0 for each vV(G). Observe that δ(G)2 by Lemma 3.1.

    (1) d(v)=3, ω(v)=1.

    Let N(v)={v1,v2,v3}. We have that d(v1)+d(v2)+d(v3)Δ+412 by Lemma 3.3. Since the neighbors of 2-vertex are both 4+-vertices, then n2(v)=0, that is d(vi)3 for i=1,2,3, and n3(v)2.

    If n3(v)=2, suppose that d(v1)=d(v2)=3, then d(v3)6. This implies that ω(v)1+2×15+35 = 0 by R1,R4. If n3(v)=1, then either n4(v)=1,n5+(v)=1 or n4(v)=0,n5+(v)=2. By R1,R2,R3,R4, we have that ω(v)1+2×15+min{15+25,2×25,25+35,2×35}=0. If n3(v)=0, then n4+(v)=3. By R1,R4, ω(v)1+2×15+3×15=0.

    (2) d(v)=4, ω(v)=0.

    If n2(v)0, then n2(v)+n3(v)2 by Lemma 3.4.

    This means that ω(v)0+3×1515n3(v)0+3×1515n3(v)n2(v)×n2(v)=0 by R1,R2.

    If n2(v)=0, then n3(v)3 by Lemma 3.8, which implies that ω(v)0+3×153×15=0 by R1,R4.

    (3) d(v)=5, ω(v)=1.

    If n2(v)0, then ω(v)1+4×1525n3(v)1+4×1525n3(v)n2(v)×n2(v)=0 by R1,R3.

    If n2(v)=0, then n3(v)4 by Lemma 3.8. This implies that ω(v)1+4×154×25=15>0 by R1,R3.

    (4) d(v)=6, ω(v)=2.

    If n2(v)0, then ω(v)2+5×1535n3(v)2+5×1535n3(v)n2(v)×n2(v)=0 by R1,R4.

    If n2(v)=0, then n3(v)5 by Lemma 3.8. This implies that ω(v)2+5×155×35=0 by R1,R4.

    (5) d(v)7, ω(v)=d(v)4.

    If n2(v)0, then ω(v)d(v)4+15×(d(v)1)35n3(v)d(v)4+15×(d(v)1)35n3(v)n2(v)×n2(v)=0 by R1,R4.

    If n2(v)=0, then ω(v)d(v)4+15×(d(v)1)35n3(v)65d(v)21535d(v)=35d(v)2150 by R1,R4.

    (6) d(v)=2, ω(v)=2.

    For convenience, let τ(uv) denote the charge transferred out of u into v according to the above rules, u,vV(G). Let N(v)={x,y}, then n2(x)d(x)2,n2(y)d(y)2 by Lemma 3.4.

    (6.1) If one of vertices in {x,y}, such as x, has n2(x) = d(x)2, then nΔ(x) = 2, n2(y) = 1, n3(y)1 and d(y) = Δ by Lemma 3.5. By R1 and R4, we have that τ(yv)ω(y)+15×(d(y)1)35n3(y)n2(y)d(y)4+15d(y)151×351=65d(y)245=65×(Δ4)245. This implies that ω(v)2+15+245=3>0 by R1.

    (6.2) n2(x)d(x)3,n2(y)d(y)3. Suppose that d(x)d(y).

    (6.2.1) d(x)9.

    Observe that n2(x)+n3(x)d(x)+d(y)Δ1 by Lemma 3.4. Note that τ(xv)ω(x)+15×(d(x)1)35n3(x)n2(x)d(x)4+15d(x)1535×(d(x)1n2(x))n2(x)=35d(x)185+35n2(x)n2(x)=35×(1+d(x)6n2(x))35×(1+d(x)6d(x)3) = 35×(23d(x)3) by R1,R4.

    Similarly, τ(yv)35×(23d(x)3). Since d(x)9, d(x)d(y), we have τ(xv)910,τ(yv)910. This implies that ω(v)2+15+2×910=0 by R1.

    (6.2.2) d(x)=8, then n2(x)d(x)3=5.

    (a) Δ9.

    Observe that n2(x)+n3(x)d(x)+d(y)Δ2d(x)2 by Lemma 3.4. Note that τ(xv)ω(x)+15×(d(x)1)35n3(x)n2(x)d(x)4+15×(d(x)1)35×(d(x)2n2(x))n2(x)=35×(1+d(x)5n2(x))35×(1+d(x)5d(x)3)=35×(22d(x)3)=2425 by R1,R4.

    If d(y)=d(x)<Δ, then we have τ(yv)35×(1+3n2(y))35×(1+35)=2425 by the similar argument above. This implies that ω(v)2+15+2×2425=325>0 by R4.

    If d(y)9, then we have n2(y)+n3(y)d(x)+d(y)Δ1d(y)2, n2(y)d(y)3 by Lemma 3.4. This means that τ(yv)35×(1+d(y)5n2(y))35×(22d(y)3) by R1 and R4. τ(yv)1 since d(y)9. So ω(v)2+15+2425+1=225>0 by R4.

    (b) Δ=8.

    Now we have d(x)=d(y)=Δ=8. Observe that n2(x)+n3(x)d(x)+d(y)Δ1d(x)1 = 7 by Lemma 3.4. If n2(x)4, then τ(xv)35×(1+2d(x)14n2(x))35×(1+24)=910 by R1,R4. Similarly, if n2(y)4, then τ(yv)910. If n2(x)5, then we have n2(x)=5 due to n2(x)d(x)3=5. Observe that n2(x)+n3(x)Δ2=6 by Lemma 3.7. This implies that τ(xv)35×(1+2d(x)13n2(x))=35×(1+35)=2425 by R1,R4. Similarly, if n2(y)5, then τ(yv)2425. Hence, ω(v)2+15+min{2×910,2×2425,910+2425}=0 by R1.

    (6.2.3) d(x)=7, then n2(x)d(x)3=4.

    Observe that n2(x)+n3(x)d(x)+d(y)Δ25 by Lemma 3.4. Note that τ(xv)35 ×(1+2d(x)12n2(x))910 by R1,R4.

    If d(y)=7, then we have that n2(y)+n3(y)d(x)+d(y)Δ2=12Δ4,n2(y)d(y)3=4 by Lemma 3.4. Note that τ(yv)ω(y)+15×(d(y)1)35n3(y)n2(y)d(y)4+15×(d(y)1)35×(4n2(y))n2(y)=35×(1+2d(y)11n2(y))35 ×(1+34)=2120 by R1,R4. We have that ω(v)2+15+910+2120=320>0 by R1.

    If d(y)8, then we have that n2(y)+n3(y)d(x)+d(y)Δ1d(y)2,n2(y)d(y)3 by Lemma 3.4.

    Note that τ(yv)ω(y)+15×(d(y)1)35n3(y)n2(y)d(y)4+15×(d(y)1)35×(d(y)2n2(y))n2(y)35×(1+d(y)5n2(y))35×(22d(y)3) by R1,R4. Since d(y)8, τ(yv)2425, we have that ω(v)2+15+910+2425=350>0 by R1.

    (6.2.4) d(x)=6, then n2(x)d(x)3=3.

    By Lemma 3.4, we have that n2(x)+n3(x)d(x)+d(y)Δ24. Note that τ(xv)35 ×(1+2d(x)11n2(x))45 by R1,R4.

    If d(y)=6, then we have that n2(y)+n3(y)d(x)+d(y)Δ2=10Δ2 by Lemma 3.4. So n2(y)2. Note that τ(yv)ω(y)+15×(d(y)1)35n3(y)n2(y)d(y)4+15×(d(y)1)35×(2n2(y))n2(y)=35×(1+2d(y)9n2(y))35 ×(1+32)=32 by R1,R4. This means that ω(v)2+15+45+32=12>0 by R1.

    If d(y)=7, then we have that n2(y)+n3(y)d(x)+d(y)Δ2=11Δ3 by Lemma 3.4. So n2(y)3. Note that τ(yv)ω(y)+15×(d(y)1)35n3(y)n2(y)d(y)4+15×(d(y)1)35×(3n2(y))n2(y)=35×(1+2d(y)10n2(y))35 ×(1+43)=75 by R1,R4. This means that ω(v)2+15+45+75=25>0 by R1.

    If d(y)8, then we have that n2(y)+n3(y)d(x)+d(y)Δ1d(y)3,n2(y)d(y)3 by Lemma 3.4.

    Note that τ(yv)ω(y)+15×(d(y)1)35n3(y)n2(y)d(y)4+15×(d(y)1)35×(d(y)3n2(y))n2(y)=35×(1+d(y)4n2(y))35×(21d(y)3) by R1,R4. Since d(y)8, τ(yv)2725, we have that ω(v)2+15+45+2725=225>0 by R1.

    (6.2.5) d(x)=5, then n2(x)d(x)3=2.

    By Lemma 3.4, we have that n2(x)+n3(x)d(x)+d(y)Δ23. Note that τ(xv)ω(x)+15×(d(x)1)25n3(x)n2(x)1+4×1525×(3n2(x))n2(x)=25+35×1n2(x)25+35×12=710 by R1,R3. Observe that d(x)+d(y)Δ+3 by Lemma 3.3, so d(y)Δ+3d(x)6.

    If d(y)=6, then we have that n2(y)+n3(y)d(x)+d(y)Δ2=9Δ1 by Lemma 3.4, which means that n2(y)=1,n3(y)=0. Note that τ(yv)ω(y)+15×(d(y)1)35n3(y)n2(y)=2+5×150×351=3 by R1,R4. So ω(v)2+15+710+3=1910>0 by R1.

    If d(y)=7, then we have that n2(y)+n3(y)d(x)+d(y)Δ2=10Δ2 by Lemma 3.4. So n2(y)2. Note that τ(yv)ω(y)+15×(d(y)1)35n3(y)n2(y)d(y)4+15×(d(y)1)35×(2n2(y))n2(y)=35×(1+5n2(y))35 ×(1+52)=2110 by R1,R4. Hence, ω(v)2+15+710+2110=1>0 by R1.

    If d(y)8, then we have that n2(y)+n3(y)d(x)+d(y)Δ1d(y)4 by Lemma 3.4. So n2(y)d(y)4. Note that τ(yv)ω(y)+15×(d(y)1)35n3(y)n2(y)d(y)4+15×(d(y)1)35×(d(y)4n2(y))n2(y)=35×(1+d(y)3n2(y))35 ×(2+1d(y)4) by R1,R4. Observe that τ(yv)>65 since d(y)8. Then ω(v)>2+15+710+65=110>0 by R1.

    (6.2.6) d(x)=4

    By Lemma 3.4, we have that n2(x)+n3(x)d(x)+d(y)Δ22.

    (a) n2(x)+n3(x)=2.

    By Lemma 3.6, we have that nΔ(x)=2,n2(y)=1,n3(y)1, and d(y)=Δ. Note that τ(yv)ω(y)+15×(d(y)1)35n3(y)n2(y)d(y)4+15d(y)151×351=65d(y)245=65(Δ4)245 by R1,R4. So ω(v)2+15+245 = 3>0 by R1.

    (b) n2(x)+n3(x)1. That is n2(x)=1,n3(x)=0.

    Note that τ(xv)ω(x)+15×(d(x)1)15n3(x)n2(x)0+3×150×151=35 by R1,R2. Observe that d(x)+d(y)Δ+3 by Lemma 3.3, so d(y)Δ+3d(x)7.

    If d(y)=7, then we have that n2(y)+n3(y)d(x)+d(y)Δ2=9Δ1 by Lemma 3.4, which means that n2(y)=1,n3(y)=0. Note that τ(yv)ω(y)+15×(d(y)1)35n3(y)n2(y)=3+6×150×351=215 by R1,R4. So ω(v)2+15+35+215=3>0 by R1.

    If d(y)8, then we have that n2(y)+n3(y)d(x)+d(y)Δ1d(y)5 by Lemma 3.4. Hence n2(y)d(y)5.

    Note that τ(yv)ω(y)+15×(d(y)1)35n3(y)n2(y)d(y)4+15×(d(y)1)35×(d(y)5n2(y))n2(y)=35×(1+d(y)2n2(y))35×(2+3d(y)5) by R1,R4. We have that τ(yv)>65 since d(y)8. Hence, ω(v)>2+15+35+65=0 by R1.

    After R1R4, we get ω(v)0, for all vV(G). For all fF(G), if d(f)=4, then ω(f)=ω(f)=d(f)4=0. If d(f)5, then we have ω(f)=d(f)4d(f)4d(f)×d(f)=0 by R4.

    In summary, we get the following contradictory formula:

    8=xV(G)F(G)ω(x)=xV(G)F(G)ω(x)0.

    The above contradiction indicates that G does not exist, so Theorem 1.1 is true.

    In this paper, we consider the acyclic chromatic index of planar graphs without 3-cycles and intersecting 4-cycles and proved that such graphs have χa(G)Δ+1 if Δ(G)8. A natural problem in context of our main result is the following:

    What is the optimal constant c such that χa(G)Δ(G)+1 for every planar graph G with g(G)c?

    This work was supported by National Natural Science Foundations of China (Grant Nos. 11771403 and 11901243)

    The authors declare no conflicts of interest.



    [1] N. Alon, C. McDiarmid, B. Reed, Acyclic coloring of graphs, Random Struct. Algor., 2 (1991), 277–288. http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/rsa.3240020303 doi: 10.1002/rsa.3240020303
    [2] M. Basavaraju, L. Chandran, N. Cohen, F. Havet, T. M¨ulle, Acyclic edge-coloring of planar graphs, SIAM J. Discrete Math., 25 (2011), 463–478. http://dx.doi.org/10.1137/090776676 doi: 10.1137/090776676
    [3] J. Fiamˇcik, The acyclic chromatic class of a graph(Russian), Math. Slovaca, 28 (1978), 139–145.
    [4] P. Fialho, B. de Lima, A. Procacci, A new bound on the acyclic edge chromatic number, Discrect Math., 343 (2020), 112037. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.disc.2020.112037 doi: 10.1016/j.disc.2020.112037
    [5] A. Fiedorowicz, Acyclic edge colouring of plane graphs, Discrete Appl. Math., 160 (2012), 1513–1523. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.dam.2012.02.018 doi: 10.1016/j.dam.2012.02.018
    [6] J. Hou, W. Wang, X. Zhang, Acyclic edge coloring of planar graphs with girth at least 5, Discrete Appl. Math., 161 (2013), 2958–2967. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.dam.2013.06.013 doi: 10.1016/j.dam.2013.06.013
    [7] L. Kirousis, J. Livieratos, The acyclic chromatic index is less than the double of the max degree, arXiv: 1901.07856v6. http://dx.doi.org/10.48550/arXiv.1901.07856
    [8] M. Molloy, B. Reed, Further algorithmic aspects of the local lemma, Proceedings of the Thirtieth Annual ACM Symposium on the Theory of Comouting, 1998,524–529. http://dx.doi.org/10.1145/276698.276866 doi: 10.1145/276698.276866
    [9] W. Wang, Q. Shu, Y. Wang, A new upper bound on the acyclic chromatic indices of planar graphs, Eur. J. Combin., 34 (2013), 338–354. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.ejc.2012.07.008 doi: 10.1016/j.ejc.2012.07.008
    [10] T. Wang, Y. Zhang, Further result on acyclic chromatic index of planar graphs, Discrete Appl. Math., 201 (2016), 228–247. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.dam.2015.07.015 doi: 10.1016/j.dam.2015.07.015
    [11] Q. Shu, W. Wang, Y. Wang, Acyclic chromatic indices of planar graphs with girth at least 4, J. Graph Theory, 73 (2013), 386–399. http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/jgt.21683 doi: 10.1002/jgt.21683
    [12] Q. Shu, Y. Chen, S. Han, G. Lin, E. Miyano, A. Zhang, Acyclic edge coloring conjecture is true on planar graphs without intersecting triangles, Theor. Comput. Sci., 882 (2021), 77–108. http://dx.doi.org/j.tcs.2021.06.017
    [13] Y. Wang, P. Sheng, Improved upper bound for acyclic chromatic index of planar graphs without 4-cycles, J. Comb. Optim., 27 (2014), 519–529. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s10878-012-9524-5 doi: 10.1007/s10878-012-9524-5
    [14] W. Wang, Q. Shu, Y. Wang, Acyclic edge coloring of planar graphs without 4-cycles, J. Comb. Optim., 25 (2013), 562–586. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s10878-012-9474-y doi: 10.1007/s10878-012-9474-y
  • Reader Comments
  • © 2022 the Author(s), licensee AIMS Press. This is an open access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0)
通讯作者: 陈斌, bchen63@163.com
  • 1. 

    沈阳化工大学材料科学与工程学院 沈阳 110142

  1. 本站搜索
  2. 百度学术搜索
  3. 万方数据库搜索
  4. CNKI搜索

Metrics

Article views(2064) PDF downloads(105) Cited by(0)

Figures and Tables

Figures(3)

Other Articles By Authors

/

DownLoad:  Full-Size Img  PowerPoint
Return
Return

Catalog