Previously, several notions of T0 and T1 objects have been studied and examined in various topological categories. In this paper, we characterize each of T0 and T1 objects in the categories of several types of bounded uniform filter spaces and examine their mutual relations, and compare that with the usual ones. Moreover, it is shown that under T0 (resp. T1) condition, the category of preuniform (resp. semiuniform) convergence spaces and the category of bornological (resp. symmetric) bounded uniform filter spaces are isomorphic. Finally, it is proved that the category of each of T0 (resp. T1) bounded uniform filter space are quotient reflective subcategories of the category of bounded uniform filter spaces.
Citation: Sana Khadim, Muhammad Qasim. Quotient reflective subcategories of the category of bounded uniform filter spaces[J]. AIMS Mathematics, 2022, 7(9): 16632-16648. doi: 10.3934/math.2022911
[1] | Muhammad Qasim, Arbaz Jehan Khan, Samirah Alsulami, Shoaib Assar . Some topological aspects of interval spaces. AIMS Mathematics, 2023, 8(2): 3826-3841. doi: 10.3934/math.2023190 |
[2] | Naveed Ahmad Malik, Sana Khyzer, Muhammad Qasim . Local Pre-Hausdorffness and D-connectedness in $ \mathcal{L} $-valued closure spaces. AIMS Mathematics, 2022, 7(5): 9261-9277. doi: 10.3934/math.2022513 |
[3] | Xiaoyuan Zhang, Meng Bao, Xinpeng Wen, Xiaoquan Xu . On weakly bounded well-filtered spaces. AIMS Mathematics, 2022, 7(9): 17026-17044. doi: 10.3934/math.2022936 |
[4] | Jie Qiong Shi, Xiao Long Xin . Ideal theory on EQ-algebras. AIMS Mathematics, 2021, 6(11): 11686-11707. doi: 10.3934/math.2021679 |
[5] | Xiaoyuan Zhang, Meng Bao, Xiaoquan Xu . On function spaces related to some kinds of weakly sober spaces. AIMS Mathematics, 2022, 7(5): 9311-9324. doi: 10.3934/math.2022516 |
[6] | Jinlei Dong, Fang Li, Longgang Sun . Derived equivalence, recollements under $ H $-Galois extensions. AIMS Mathematics, 2023, 8(2): 3210-3225. doi: 10.3934/math.2023165 |
[7] | Mona Aaly Kologani, Rajab Ali Borzooei, Hee Sik Kim, Young Bae Jun, Sun Shin Ahn . Construction of some algebras of logics by using intuitionistic fuzzy filters on hoops. AIMS Mathematics, 2021, 6(11): 11950-11973. doi: 10.3934/math.2021693 |
[8] | Seçil Çeken, Cem Yüksel . Generalizations of strongly hollow ideals and a corresponding topology. AIMS Mathematics, 2021, 6(12): 12986-13003. doi: 10.3934/math.2021751 |
[9] | Xiaolin Xie, Hui Kou . The Cartesian closedness of c-spaces. AIMS Mathematics, 2022, 7(9): 16315-16327. doi: 10.3934/math.2022891 |
[10] | Dina Abuzaid, Samer Al Ghour . Three new soft separation axioms in soft topological spaces. AIMS Mathematics, 2024, 9(2): 4632-4648. doi: 10.3934/math.2024223 |
Previously, several notions of T0 and T1 objects have been studied and examined in various topological categories. In this paper, we characterize each of T0 and T1 objects in the categories of several types of bounded uniform filter spaces and examine their mutual relations, and compare that with the usual ones. Moreover, it is shown that under T0 (resp. T1) condition, the category of preuniform (resp. semiuniform) convergence spaces and the category of bornological (resp. symmetric) bounded uniform filter spaces are isomorphic. Finally, it is proved that the category of each of T0 (resp. T1) bounded uniform filter space are quotient reflective subcategories of the category of bounded uniform filter spaces.
It is well-known that general topology fails to have the concepts of uniformity (uniform convergence and uniform continuity), hereditary of quotients, Cartesian closedness, Cauchy continuity, total boundedness, and completeness. Therefore, several attempts has been made to overcome these deficiencies including Kent convergence spaces [27], quasiuniform spaces [19], generalized topological spaces [17], seminearness spaces [26] and nearness spaces [22]. But none of them have led to fulfilling all the above properties. In 1995, Preuss [35] developed the concept of semiuniform convergence spaces (a basic structure in the domain of convenient topology) that solves almost all the flaws that appeared in Top (category of topological spaces and continuous maps). Moreover, by exempting symmetric condition from the semi-uniform convergence spaces, Preuss obtained preuniform convergence spaces and as a special case semiuniform convergence spaces Pre. Later, in 2018 and 2019, Leseberg [31,33] extended the idea of Preuss and defined his concept on bounded structures in terms of bounded uniform filter spaces. Interestingly, not only PUConv (the category of preuniform convergence spaces and uniformly continuous maps) are embedded in b-UFIL (the category of bounded uniform filter spaces and bounded continuous maps) but also BORN (category of bornological spaces and continuous maps that are embedded in bounded spaces) can easily be embedded in b-UFIL as its subcategories. Also, the category b-UFIL forms a strong topological universe [31].
Classical separation axioms of general topology have many applications in almost all areas of Mathematics. In algebraic topology, an alternative characterization of locally semi-simple coverings in terms of light morphisms are achieved with the help of classical T0 [24]. Furthermore, in lambda calculus and denotational semantics of programming language, various topological models have been built by using the T0 separation axiom [38,39] where Hausdorff topological spaces failed to do so. Other treatments with these axioms can be found in digital topology where they are used to characterize the digital line, in computer graphs and image processing and to construct cellular complex [21,28,29]. After stating such significance of T0 and T1 separation properties, several mathematicians have extended this idea to arbitrary topological categories [2,15,20,23,34] and the generic point method of topos theory by Johnstone has been used [25] due to the fact that in topos theory, generally speaking, the objects may not have points, yet, they always have a generic element. One of their primarily usage is to define each of T3, T4, regular, completely regular, and normal objects in an abstract topological category [6].
The main concepts in general topology depend upon notion of closedness. Thus, several generalizations of the classical separation axioms at some point p (local considering) have been inspected in [2] where the primary purpose of this generalization was to interpret the notion of closed sets and strongly closed sets in arbitrary set based topological categories. Moreover, the notions of compactness, Hausdorffness and perfectness have been generalized by using these closed and strongly closed sets in any topological category over sets [2,7]. Further, they are suitable for the formation of closure operators [16] in several well-known topological categories [10,12,18,37] and used to extend several fundamental theorems of general topology including Urysohn lemma and Tietze extension theorem [13,14].
The salient objectives of this study are stated as under:
(i) To characterize local ¯T0, local T′0 and local T1 objects in the category of bounded uniform filter spaces, and examine their mutual relationship;
(ii) To give the characterization of ¯T0, T′0 andT1 objects in the category of bounded uniform filter spaces, and examine their mutual relationship;
(iii) To examine that under conditions of T0 and T1, preuniform (respectively semiuniform) spaces are isomorphic to bornological (respectively symmetric) bounded uniform filter spaces;
(iv) To examine the quotient-reflective properties of several bounded uniform filter spaces.
For arbitrary topological categories G and H, the functor F:G→H is said to be a topological functor, or the category G is said to be a topological category over H if F is concrete (amnestic and faithful), F consists of small fibers, and there exists an initial lift (or equivalently, a final lift) corresponding to every F-source [1,36].
A filter σ on a set A is a non-empty collection such that finite intersection of elements of σ is in σ, and every superset of a set in σ is in σ. If ∅∈σ then σ is an improper filter otherwise it is a proper filter. We write F(A) for the set of all filters on A. Let v∈A, then [v]=˙v=[{v}]={W⊂A:v∈W} is a filter on A. Similarly, [U]={W⊂A:W⊃U} is a filter on A.
Definition 2.1. (cf. [31]) Let X be a non-empty set, ΘX be a non-empty subset of P(X) and ψ⊂F(X×X) be a non-empty set of uniform filters on the cartesian product of X with itself. A pair (ΘX,ψ) is said to be a bounded uniform filter structure (or b-UFIL structure) on X and the corresponding triplet (X,ΘX,ψ) is known as bounded uniform filter space (or b-UFIL space) on X if the following axioms hold:
(b-UFIL1) E′⊂E∈ΘX implies E′∈ΘX;
(b-UFIL2) x∈X implies {x}∈ΘX;
(b-UFIL3) E∈ΘX∖∅ implies [E]×[E]∈ψ;
(b-UFIL4) σ∈ψ and σ⊂σ′∈F(X×X) implies σ′∈ψ.
A b-UFIL space (X,ΘX,ψ) is a symmetric b-UFIL space provided that the following axiom holds:
(b-UFIL5) σ∈ψ implies σ−1∈ψ.
A symmetric b-UFIL space (X,ΘX,ψ) is a symmetric bounded uniform limit space provided that the following axiom holds:
(b-UFIL6) σ∈ψ and σ′∈ψ implying σ∩σ′∈ψ.
A b-UFIL space (X,ΘX,ψ) is a crossbounded uniform filter space provided it satisfies the following condition:
(crb) σ∈ψ implies E×E∈σ for some E∈ΘX.
If we denote by CROSSb-UFIL the corresponding defined full subcategory of b-UFIL, then it is clear that BOUND and CROSSb-UFIL are isomorphic. Hence we can introduce the following as:
A cross bounded uniform filter space (X,ΘX,ψ) is a bornological b-UFIL space provided that the following axiom holds:
(b-UFIL7) E,E′∈ΘX implying E∪E′∈ΘX.
Let (X,ΘX,ψX) and (Y,ΘY,ψY) be two b-UFIL spaces and h:X→Y be a map. Then h is called bounded uniformly continuous (or buc) map if E∈ΘX implies h(E)∈ΘY; and σ∈ψX implies (h×h)(σ)∈ψY; where (h×h)(σ):={V⊂Y×Y:∃U∈σ∣(h×h)[U]⊂V} with (h×h)[U]:={(h×h)(x,y):(x,y)∈U}={(h(x),h(y)):(x,y)∈U}.
We denote b-UFIL as category of b-UFIL spaces and buc maps. Similarly, sb-UFIL (respectively LIMsb-UFIL) as category of symmetric b-UFIL spaces (respectively category of symmetric b-UFIL limit spaces) and buc maps. Furthermore, BONb-UFIL is the category of bornological b-UFIL spaces and buc maps.
(i) For given a family of b-UFIL spaces (Xj,ΘXj,ψj)j∈I and maps (hj:X→Xj)j∈I. The initial b-UFIL structure on X is represented by (ΘX,ψ), where ΘX:={E⊂X:hj[E]∈ΘXj,∀j∈I} and ψ:={σ∈F(X2):(hj×hj)(σ)∈ψj,∀j∈I} with X2:=X×X.
(ii) A b-UFIL structure on X is indiscrete if (ΘX,ψ):=(P(X),F(X2)).
(iii) For given a family of b-UFIL spaces (Xj,ΘXj,ψj)j∈I and maps (hj:Xj→X)j∈I. The final b-UFIL structure on X is represented by (ΘX,ψ), where ΘX:={E⊂X:∃i∈I,∃Ej∈ΘXj:E⊂hj[Ej]}∪DX:={∅}∪{{a}:a∈X} and ψ:={σ∈F(X2):∃j∈I,∃σj∈ψj:(hj×hj)(σj)⊂σ}∪{[x]×[x]:x∈X}∪{P(X2)}.
(iv) A b-UFIL structure on X is discrete if (ΘX,ψ):=(DX,ψdis), where ψdis:={[x]×[x]:x∈X}∪{P(X2)}.
Remark 2.1. (i) A bornological b-UFIL structure on X is discrete if (ΘX,ψ):=(DXborn,ψdis), where DXborn:={E⊂X:E is finite} [33].
(ii) The category PUConv is isomorphic to DISb-UFIL (category of discrete b-UFIL spaces and buc maps) [31].
(iii) The category SUConv is isomorphic to DISsb-UFIL (category of discrete symmetric b-UFIL spaces and buc maps) [31].
In general topology, all the basic concepts including compactness, connectedness, perfectness, soberness, Hausdorffness and closure operators can be defined in terms of closedness. In order to define these notions of closedness in categorical language, Baran [2] introduced local T0 and local T1 of topology in topological category using initial, final lifts and discrete objects. Moreover, these notion of closedness (strongly closedness) are used to extend several famous theorems of general topology such as Urysohn lemma and Tietze extension theorem.
In this section, we recall definitions of local T0 and local T1 b-UFIL spaces (at some fixed point p). Let X be any set and p∈X. We define the wedge product of X at p as the two disjoint copies of X at p and denote it as X⋁pX. For a point x∈X⋁pX, we write it as x1 if x belongs to the first component of the wedge product; otherwise, we write x2 that is in the second component, where X2 is the cartesian product of X.
Definition 3.1. (cf. [2])
(i) A map Ap:X⋁pX⟶X2 is said to be principal p-axis map provided that
Ap(xj):={(x,p),j=1,(p,x),j=2. |
(ii) A map Sp:X⋁pX⟶X2 is said to be skewed p-axis map provided that
Sp(xj):={(x,x),j=1,(p,x),j=2. |
(iii) A map ∇p:X⋁pX⟶X is said to be fold map at p provided that
∇p(xj):=x,j=1,2. |
Assume that F:G⟶Set is a topological functor, X∈Obj(G) with FX=E and p∈E.
Definition 3.2. (cf. [2])
(i) X is ¯T0 at p provided that initial lift of F-source {E⋁pEAp→F(X2)=E2 and E⋁pE∇p→FDE=E} is discrete.
(ii) X is T′0 at p provided that initial lift of F-source {E⋁pEid→F(X⋁pX)=E⋁pE and E⋁pE∇p→FDE=E} is discrete, where X⋁pX represents the wedge product in G, i.e., final lift of F-sink {FX=Ei1,i2→E⋁pE}, where i1 and i2 denote the canonical injections.
(iii) X is T1 at p provided that initial lift of F-source {E⋁pESp→F(X2)=E2 and E⋁pE∇p→FDE=E} is discrete.
Remark 3.1. (i) In Top, ¯T0 and T′0 at p (respectively T1 at p) are equivalent to the classical T0 at p (respectively the classical T1 at p), i.e., for each x∈X with x≠p, there exists a neighborhood Nx of x not containing p or (respectively and) there exists a neighborhood Np of p not containing x [5].
(ii) A topological space X is T0 (respectively T1) if and only if X is T0 (respectively T1) at p for all p∈X [5].
(iii) Let U:G→Set be a topological functor, X∈Obj(G) and p∈U(X) be a retract of X. If X is ¯T0 (respectively T1) at p, then X is T′0 at p but not conversely in general [3].
(iv) Let U:G→Set be normalized and X∈Obj(G) with p∈U(X). If X PreT2 object at p, then X is ¯T0 at p iff X is T1 at p [3,8].
Theorem 3.1. Let (X,ΘX,ψ) be a b-UFIL space and p∈X. Then (X,ΘX,ψ) is ¯T0 at p iff for all x∈X with x≠p, the following hold.
(i) {x,p}∉ΘX;
(ii) [x]×[p]∉ψ or [p]×[x]∉ψ;
(iii) ([x]×[x])∩([p]×[p])∉ψ.
Proof. Let (X,ΘX,ψ) be ¯T0 at p. We shall prove that the above conditions (ⅰ)–(ⅲ) hold. Let {x,p}∈ΘX for x≠p and W={x1,x2}∈ΘX∨pX. Since ∇pW={x}∈DX, and πkApW={x,p}∈ΘX for k=1,2, where πk:X2→X for k=1,2 are the projection maps. Since (X,ΘX,ψ) is ¯T0 at p, by the Definitions 2.2 and 3.2, we get a contradiction. Hence, {x,p}∉ΘX.
Next, suppose that [x]×[p]∈ψ for some x≠p. Let σ=[x1]×[x2]. Clearly, (∇p×∇p)σ=[x]×[x]∈ψdis, (π1Ap×π1Ap)σ=[x]×[p]∈ψ and (π2Ap×π2Ap)σ=[p]×[x]∈ψ, a contradiction. It follows that [x]×[p]∉ψ or [p]×[x]∉ψ.
Further, if ([x]×[x])∩([p]×[p])∈ψ for some x≠p. Let σ=([x1]×[x1])∩([x2]×[x2]). Since (∇p×∇p)σ=[x]×[x]∈ψdis, (π1Ap×π1Ap)σ=([x]×[x])∩([p]×[p])∈ψ and (π2Ap×π2Ap)σ=([p]×[p])∩([x]×[x])∈ψ, a contradiction since (X,ΘX,ψ) is ¯T0 at p. Thus, ([x]×[x])∩([p]×[p])∉ψ.
Conversely, let us assume that the conditions (ⅰ)–(ⅲ) hold. Let (ΘX∨pX,¯ψ) be the initial structure induced by Ap:X∨pX→(X2,ΘX2,ψ2) and ∇p:X∨pX→(X,DX,ψdis), where (ΘX2,ψ2) represents the product b-UFIL structure on X2 and (DX,ψdis) the discrete b-UFIL structure on X, respectively. We show that (ΘX∨pX,¯ψ) is the discrete b-UFIL structure on X∨pX. Let W∈ΘX∨pX and ∇pW∈DX.
If ∇pW=∅, then W=∅. Suppose ∇pW≠∅, it follows that ∇pW={x} for some x∈X. If x=p, then W={p}. Suppose x≠p. It follows that W={x1},{x2} or {x1,x2}. The case, W={x1,x2} cannot happen since πkApW={x,p}∉ΘX (k=1,2) by the assumption. Hence, W={x1},{x2} and consequently, ΘX∨pX=DX∨pX, the discrete b-UFIL structure on X∨pX.
Next, let σ∈¯ψ. By Definition 2(i), (∇p×∇p)σ∈DX and (πkAp×πkAp)σ∈ψ for k=1,2. We need to show that σ=[xi]×[xi] (i=1,2), σ=[p]×[p] or σ=[∅]=P((X∨pX)×(X∨pX)).
If (∇p×∇p)σ=[∅], then σ=[∅]=P((X∨pX)×(X∨pX)). Suppose (∇p×∇p)σ=[x]×[x] for some x∈X. If x=p, then σ=[p]×[p].
If x≠p, then (∇p×∇p)σ=[x]×[x], then {x1,x2}×{x1,x2}∈σ. Thus there is a finite subset N0 of σ such that σ=[N0]. Clearly, N0⊆{x1,x2}×{x1,x2} and if i≠j, then {{xi}×{xj}}≠N0 and {{x1}×{x1},{x2}×{x2}}≠N0 since in particular for k=1, i=1, and j=2, (π1Ap×π1Ap)([x1]×[x2])=[x]×[p]∉ψ and (π1Ap×π1Ap)(([x1]×[x1])∩([x2]×[x2]))=([x]×[x])∩([p]×[p]) ∉ψ by using the second and the third conditions respectively.
Therefore, we must have σ=[xi]×[xi] (i=1,2) and consequently, by Definitions 3.2, 2.1 and 2.2, (X,ΘX,ψ) is ¯T0 at p.
Theorem 3.2. Let (X,ΘX,ψ) be a b-UFIL space and p∈X. Then (X,ΘX,ψ) is T1 at p iff for all x∈X with x≠p, the followings hold.
(i) {x,p}∉ΘX;
(ii) [x]×[p]∉ψ and [p]×[x]∉ψ;
(iii) ([x]×[x])∩([p]×[p])∉ψ.
Proof. The proof is analogous to the proof of Theorem 3.1 by using the skewed p-axis map Sp instead of the principal p-axis map Ap.
Example 3.1. Let X={k,l,m} and (ΘX,ψ) be a b-UFIL structure on X with ΘX={∅,{k},{l},{m}} and ψ={[∅],[k]×[k],[l]×[l],[m]×[m],[k]×[l],[k]×[m]}. Then, (X,ΘX,ψ) is ¯T0 at k but not T1 at k.
Theorem 3.3. All b-UFIL spaces are T′0 at p.
Proof. Suppose (X,ΘX,ψ) is a b-UFIL space and p∈X. By Definition 2.2(ⅱ), we show that for any W∈ΘX∨pX, W⊂ij(V) (j=1or2) for some V∈ΘX, and ∇pW∈DX, and for any σ∈F((X∨pX)×(X∨pX)), σ⊃(ij×ij)α (j=1or2) for some α∈ψ and (∇p×∇p)σ∈ψdis. Then W=∅, {p} or {xk} for k=1,2.
If ∇pW=∅, then W=∅. Let ∇pW≠∅. It follows that ∇pW={x} for some x∈X.
If x=p, then ∇pW={p}, it follows that W={p}.
Suppose x≠p, it follows that W={x1}, {x2} or {x1,x2}. If W={x1,x2}, then {x1,x2}⊂i1(V) for some V∈ΘX which shows that x2 should be in first component of the wedge product X∨pX, a contradiction. In similar manner, {x1,x2}⊄i2(V) for some V∈ΘX. Hence, W≠{x1,x2}. Thus, we must have W={xk} for k=1,2 only and consequently, ΘX∨pX=DX∨pX, the discrete b-UFIL structure on X∨pX.
Next, for any σ∈F((X∨pX)×(X∨pX)), if (∇p×∇p)σ=[∅], then σ=[∅]=P((X∨pX)×(X∨pX)).
Now, assume that (∇p×∇p)σ=[x]×[x] for some x∈X. If x=p, then (∇p×∇p)σ=[p]×[p], and consequently σ=[p]×[p].
Suppose that x≠p, then (∇p×∇p)σ= [x]×[x], hence {x1,x2}×{x1,x2}∈σ. Thus there exists a finite subset M of σ such that σ=[M]. Clearly, M⊆{x1,x2}×{x1,x2} and if k≠l, then {{xk}×{xl}}≠M and {{x1}×{x1},{x2}×{x2}}≠M. Suppose that M={{xk}×{xl}}, then for k=1, l=2, and j=1 (respectively j=2), [x1]×[x2]⊃(i1×i1)α for some α∈ψ. It follows that (x1,x2)∈(i1×i1)(U) for all U∈α, which implies that x2 (respectively x1) is in the first (respectively second) component of the wedge product X∨pX, a contradiction. In similar manner, if M={{x1}×{x1},{x2}×{x2}}, then for j=1 (respectively j=2), (([x1]×[x1])∩([x2]×[x2]))⊃(i1×i1)α for some α∈ψ. It follows that {(x1,x1),(x2,x2)}∈(i1×i1)(U) for all U∈α, which implies that x2 (respectively x1) is in the first (respectively second) component of the product X∨pX, a contradiction.
Thus, we must have σ=[xk]×[xk] (k=1,2) and consequently, by Definitions 3.2, 2.2 and Theorems 3.1, 3.2, (X,ΘX,ψ) is T′0 at p.
Corollary 3.1. Let (X,ΘX,ψ) be a symmetric b-UFIL space and p∈X, then the following statements are equivalent:
(i) X is ¯T0 at p.
(ii) X is T1 at p.
(iii) {x,p}∉ΘX; [x]×[p]∉ψ; and ([x]×[x])∩([p]×[p])∉ψ.
Proof. The proof of the corollary can be easily deduced from Theorems 3.1, 3.2 and Definition 2.1.
Corollary 3.2. Let (X,ΘX,ψ) be a symmetric b-UFIL limit space and p∈X be any point, then the following statements are equivalent:
(i) X is ¯T0 at p.
(ii) X is T1 at p.
(iiii) {x,p}∉ΘX; and [x]×[p]∉ψ.
Proof. The proof of the corollary can be easily deduced from Theorems 3.1, 3.2 and Definition 2.1.
In this section, we recall the definitions of T0 and T1 b-UFIL spaces.
To generalize the classical T0 objects, various approaches have been discussed by Topologists since 1971 such as Brümmer, Marny, Hoffman, Harvey and Baran in [2,4,15,20,23,34,40]. In addition, the relationships between several forms of generalized T0 objects in topological category have been examined in [4,40]. One of the main reasons for this generalization was to define Hausdorff objects in arbitrary topological categories [2]. But also T0 is used to define non-T2 spaces such as sober spaces [11] that are used in theoretical computer science. Further, a generalization of the classical T1 objects of topology in topological categories has been investigated by Baran [2] in 1991. One of its important uses is to define each of T3, T4, regular, completely regular, and normal objects in an abstract topological category [6]. Baran's approach was to characterize these separation axioms in terms of their initial and final lifts, and discreteness.
Since points do not make sense in topos theory, Baran [2] used the generic element method defined by Johnstone [25] to characterize separation axioms that make sense in topos theory as well, where the wedge product X⋁pX at p can be replaced by X2⋁ΔX2 at diagonal Δ.
Definition 4.1. (cf. [2])
(i) A map A:X2⋁ΔX2⟶X3 is called principal axis map provided that
A((x,y)j):={(x,y,x),j=1,(x,x,y),j=2. |
(ii) A map S:X2⋁ΔX2⟶X3 is called skewed axis map provided that
S((x,y)j):={(x,y,y),j=1,(x,x,y),j=2. |
(iii) A map ∇:X2⋁ΔX2⟶X2 is called fold map provided that
∇((x,y)j):=(x,y),j=1,2, |
where X2⋁ΔX2 is the wedge product of X2 diagonally intersected with X2, and any element (x,y)∈X2⋁ΔX2 is written as (x,y)1 (respectively (x,y)1) if it lies in the first (respectively second) component of X2⋁ΔX2. Clearly, (x,y)1=(x,y)2 if and only if x=y.
Definition 4.2. Let F:G⟶Set be a topological functor, X∈Obj(G) with FX=E.
(i) X is ¯T0 provided that the initial lift of the F-source {E2⋁ΔE2A→F(X3)=E3 and E2⋁ΔE2∇→FD(E2)=E2} is discrete [2].
(ii) X is T′0 provided that the initial lift of the F-source {E2⋁ΔE2id→F(E2⋁ΔE2)′=E2⋁ΔE2 and E2⋁ΔE2∇→FD(E2)=E2} is discrete, where (E2⋁ΔE2)′ is the final lift of the F-sink {F(X2)=E2i1,i2→E2⋁ΔE2} [2,4].
(iii) X is called T0 property provided that X doesn't contain an indiscrete subspace with at least two points [34,40].
(iv) X is T1 provided that the initial lift of the F-source {E2⋁ΔE2S→F(X3)=E3 and E2⋁ΔE2∇→FD(E2)=E2} is discrete [2].
Remark 4.1. (i) In Top, all T0, ¯T0 and T′0 (respectively T1) are equivalent to the classical T0 (respectively the classical T1), i.e., for each x,y∈X with x≠y, there exists a neighborhood Nx of x not containing y or (respectively and) there exists a neighborhood Ny of y not containing x [5].
(ii) In any topological category, ¯T0⟹T′0 but not conversely in general. Also, each of ¯T0 and T′0 objects has no relation with T0 object [4]. For Example, ¯T0 could be all objects such as in Born [4], and ¯T0⟹T0⟹T′0 such as in SUConv [9] and ¯T0=T0⟹T′0 such as in Lim [4].
(iii) Let U:G→ Set be a topological functor and X∈Obj(G). If X∈PreT2(G), then X is ¯T0 iff X is T1, where PreT2(G) is the category of PreT2 objects [8].
Theorem 4.1. Let (X,ΘX,ψ) be a b-UFIL space. (X,ΘX,ψ) is ¯T0 iff for all x,y∈X with x≠y, the following hold:
(i) {x,y}∉ΘX;
(ii) [x]×[y]∉ψ or [y]×[x]∉ψ;
(iii) ([x]×[x])∩([y]×[y])∉ψ.
Proof. Let (X,ΘX,ψ) be ¯T0. We shall prove that the above conditions (ⅰ)–(ⅲ) hold. Let {x,y}∈ΘX for x≠y and W={(x,y)1,(x,y)2}∈ΘX2∨ΔX2. Since ∇W={(x,y)}∈DX2, π1AW={x}∈ΘX, and πkAW={x,y}∈ΘX for k=2,3, where πk:X3→X2 for k=1,2,3 are the projection maps. Since (X,ΘX,ψ) is ¯T0, by the Definitions 2.2 and 4.2, we get a contradiction. Hence, {x,y}∉ΘX.
Next, suppose that [x]×[y]∈ψ for some x≠y. Let σ=[(x,y)1]×[(x,y)2]. Clearly, (∇×∇)σ=[(x,y)]×[(x,y)]∈ψ2dis, (π1A×π1A)σ=[x]×[x]∈ψ, (π2A×π2A)σ=[y]×[x]∈ψ, and (π3A×π3A)σ=[x]×[y]∈ψ, a contradiction. It follows that [x]×[y]∉ψ or [y]×[x]∉ψ.
Further, if ([x]×[x])∩([y]×[y])∈ψ for some x≠y. Let σ=([(x,y)1]×[(x,y)1])∩([(x,y)2]×[(x,y)2]). Since (∇×∇)σ=[(x,y)]×[(x,y)]∈ψ2dis, (π1A×π1A)σ=[x]×[x]∈ψ, (π2A×π2A)σ=([y]×[y])∩([x]×[x])∈ψ, and (π3A×π3A)σ=([x]×[x])∩([y]×[y])∈ψ, a contradiction since (X,ΘX,ψ) is ¯T0. Thus, ([x]×[x])∩([y]×[y])∉ψ.
Conversely, suppose that the conditions (ⅰ)–(ⅲ) hold. Let (ΘX2∨ΔX2,¯ψ) be the initial structure induced by A:X2∨ΔX2→(X3,ΘX3,ψ3) and ∇:X2∨ΔX2→(X2,DX2,ψ2dis), where (ΘX3,ψ3) represents the product b-UFIL structure on X3 and (DX2,ψ2dis) the discrete b-UFIL structure on X2, respectively. We show that (ΘX2∨ΔX2,¯ψ) is a discrete b-UFIL structure on X2∨ΔX2. Let W∈ΘX2∨ΔX2 and ∇W∈DX2.
If ∇W=∅, then W=∅. Suppose ∇W≠∅, it follows that ∇W={(x,y)} for some (x,y)∈X2. Suppose x≠y. It follows that W={(x,y)1} or {(x,y)2} or {(x,y)1,(x,y)2}. The case, W={(x,y)1,(x,y)2} cannot happen since π1AW={x}∈ΘX but πkAW={x,y}∉ΘX (k=2,3) by the assumption. Hence, W={(x,y)1} or {(x,y)2} and consequently, ΘX2∨ΔX2=DX2∨ΔX2, the discrete b-UFIL structure on X2∨ΔX2.
Next, let σ∈¯ψ. By Definition 2.2(ⅰ), (∇×∇)σ∈DX2 and (πkA×πkA)σ∈ψ for k=1,2,3. We need to prove that σ=[(x,y)i]×[(x,y)i] (i=1,2,3), or σ=[∅]=P((X2∨ΔX2)×(X2∨ΔX2)).
If (∇×∇)σ=[∅], then σ=[∅]=P((X2∨ΔX2)×(X2∨ΔX2)). Suppose (∇×∇)σ=[(x,y)]×[(x,y)] for some (x,y)∈X2. If x≠y, then (∇×∇)σ= [(x,y)]×[(x,y)], hence {(x,y)1,(x,y)2}×{(x,y)1,(x,y)2}∈σ. Thus, there is a finite subset N0 of σ such that σ=[N0]. Clearly, N0⊆{(x,y)1,(x,y)2}×{(x,y)1,(x,y)2} and if i≠j, then it can be easily seen that N0≠{{(x,y)i}×{(x,y)j}} by the second condition and that by the third condition N0≠{{(x,y)1}×{(x,y)1},{(x,y)2}×{(x,y)2}}.
Therefore, we must have σ=[(x,y)i]×[(x,y)i] (i=1,2) and consequently, by Definitions 4.2, 2.1 and 2.2, (X,ΘX,ψ) is ¯T0.
Theorem 4.2. Let (X,ΘX,ψ) be a b-UFIL space. (X,ΘX,ψ) is T0 iff for all x,y∈X with x≠y, the following hold:
(i) {x,y}∉ΘX;
(ii) ([x]×[x])∩([y]×[y])∉ψ.
Proof. Let (X,ΘX,ψ) be T0, and {x,y}∈ΘX, and [{x,y}]×[{x,y}]∈ψ for some x,y∈X with x≠y. Suppose that W={x,y}. Note that (W,ΘW,ψW) is the subspace of (X,ΘX,ψ), where (ΘW,ψW) is the initial b-UFIL structure on W induced by the inclusion map i:W→X. By Definition 2.2(ⅰ), for any B⊂W, B∈ΘW precisely when i(B)=B∈ΘX, and for α∈F(W×W), α∈ψW precisely when (i×i)α=α∈ψ. Specifically, for B=W={x,y}, i(W)=W∈ΘX and for α=[W]×[W]=[{x,y}]×[{x,y}]=([x]×[x])∩([y]×[y]), (i×i)α=[W]×[W]∈ψ, by the assumption. It follows that (ΘW,ψW)=(P(W),F(W×W)), the indiscrete b-UFIL structure on W, a contradiction. Therefore, {x,y}∉ΘX and ([x]×[x])∩([y]×[y])∉ψ.
Conversely, suppose that {x,y}∉ΘX and ([x]×[x])∩([y]×[y])∉ψ for all x,y∈X with x≠y. We show that the initial structure (ΘW,ψW) is not an indiscrete b-UFIL structure on W. Assume that W={x,y}⊂X. By the assumption and using the Definition 2.2(ⅰ), {x,y}∉ΘW and ([x]×[x])∩([y]×[y])∉ψW. Thus, (W,ΘW,ψW) is not an indiscrete bounded uniform subspace of (X,ΘX,ψ) and therefore by the Definition 4.2(ⅲ), (X,ΘX,ψ) is T0.
Theorem 4.3. Let (X,ΘX,ψ) be a b-UFIL space. (X,ΘX,ψ) is T1 iff for all x,y∈X with x≠y, the following hold:
(i) {x,y}∉ΘX;
(ii) [x]×[y]∉ψ and [y]×[x]∉ψ;
(iii) ([x]×[x])∩([y]×[y])∉ψ.
Proof. The proof is analogous to the proof of Theorem 4.1 by using the skewed axis map S instead of the principal axis map A.
Example 4.1. Let X={a,b,c} and (ΘX,ψ) be a b-UFIL structure on X with ΘX={∅,{a},{b},{c}} and ψ={[∅],[a]×[a],[b]×[b],[c]×[c],[a]×[b],[a]×[c],[b]×[c]}. Then, (X,ΘX,ψ) is ¯T0 but not T1 b-UFIL space.
Theorem 4.4. All b-UFIL spaces are T′0.
Proof. Suppose (X,ΘX,ψ) is a b-UFIL space. By Definition 4.2(ⅱ), we show that for any W∈ΘX2∨ΔX2, W⊂ij(V) (j=1or2) for some V∈ΘX2, and ∇W∈DX2, and for any σ∈F((X2∨ΔX2)×(X2∨ΔX2)), σ⊃(ij×ij)α (j=1or2) for some α∈ψ2 and (∇×∇)σ∈ψ2dis. Then W=∅, {p} or {xk} for k=1,2.
If ∇pW=∅, then W=∅. Let ∇pW≠∅. It follows that ∇pW={(x,y)} for some x∈X.
Suppose x≠y, it follows that W={(x,y)1} or {(x,y)2} or {(x,y)1,(x,y)2}. If W={(x,y)1,(x,y)2}, then {(x,y)1,(x,y)2}⊂i1(V) for some V∈ΘX2 which shows that (x,y)2 must be in the first component of X2∨ΔX2, a contradiction. Similarly, {(x,y)1,(x,y)2}⊄i2(V) for some V∈ΘX2. Hence, W≠{(x,y)1,(x,y)2}. Thus, we must have W={(x,y)k} for k=1,2 only and consequently, ΘX2∨ΔX2=DX2∨ΔX2, the discrete b-UFIL structure on X2∨ΔX2.
Next, for σ∈F((X2∨ΔX2)×(X2∨ΔX2)), if (∇×∇)σ=[∅], then σ=[∅]=P((X2∨ΔX2)×(X2∨ΔX2)). Now, assume that (∇×∇)σ=[(x,y)]×[(x,y)] for some (x,y)∈X2. Suppose that x≠y, then {(x,y)1,(x,y)2}×{(x,y)1,(x,y)2}∈σ. Thus, there exists a finite subset M of σ such that σ=[M]. Clearly, M⊆{(x,y)1,(x,y)2}×{(x,y)1,(x,y)2} and if k≠l, then {{(x,y)k}×{(x,y)l}}≠M and {{(x,y)1}×{(x,y)1},{(x,y)2}×{(x,y)2}}≠M. Suppose that M={{(x,y)k}×{(x,y)l}}, then for k=1, l=2, and j=1 (resp. j=2), [(x,y)1]×[(x,y)2]⊃(i1×i1)α for some α∈ψ. It follows that ((x,y)1,(x,y)2)∈(i1×i1)(U) for all U∈α, which implies that (x,y)2 (resp. (x,y)1) is in the first (resp. second) component of X2∨ΔX2, a contradiction. Similarly, if M={{(x,y)1}×{(x,y)1},{(x,y)2}×{(x,y)2}}, then for j=1 (resp. j=2), (([(x,y)1]×[(x,y)1])∩([(x,y)2]×[(x,y)2]))⊃(i1×i1)α for some α∈ψ. It follows that {((x,y)1,(x,y)1),((x,y)2,(x,y)2)}∈(i1×i1)(U) for all U∈α, which implies that (x,y)2 (resp. (x,y)1) is in the first (resp. second) component of X2∨ΔX2, a contradiction.
Thus, we must have σ=[(x,y)k]×[(x,y)k] (k=1,2) and consequently, by the Definitions 4.2, 2.2, and Theorems 4.1, 4.3, (X,ΘX,ψ) is T′0.
Remark 4.2. Let X be a b-UFIL space.
(i) By Theorems 3.1 and 4.1, X is ¯T0 iff X is ¯T0 at p, for all p∈X.
(ii) By Theorems 3.2 and 4.3, X is T1 iff X is T1 at p, for all p∈X.
(iii) By Theorem 3.3 and 4.4, X is T′0 iff X is T′0 at p, for all p∈X.
(iv) By Theorems 4.1–4.4, T1 ⟹ ¯T0 ⟹ T0 ⟹ T′0, but the converse does not hold in general.
Corollary 4.1. Let (X,ΘX,ψ) be a bornological b-UFIL space. Then, (X,ΘX,ψ) is ¯T0 iff for all x,y∈X with x≠y, the following hold:
(i) [x]×[y]∉ψ or [y]×[x]∉ψ;
(ii) ([x]×[x])∩([y]×[y])∉ψ.
Proof. By using the similar argument in Theorem 4.1, and by applying Remark 2.1(ⅰ), we obtain the claim.
Corollary 4.2. Let (X,ΘX,ψ) be a bornological b-UFIL space. Then, (X,ΘX,ψ) is T1 iff for all x,y∈X with x≠y, the following hold:
(i) [x]×[y]∉ψ and [y]×[x]∉ψ;
(ii) ([x]×[x])∩([y]×[y])∉ψ.
Proof. By using the similar argument in Theorem 4.1, applying Remark 2.1(ⅰ), and replacing the mapping S by mapping A, we get the results.
Corollary 4.3. Let (X,ΘX,ψ) be a symmetric b-UFIL space, then the following statements are equivalent:
(i) X is ¯T0.
(ii) X is T1.
(iii) For all x,y∈X with x≠y, {x,y}∉ΘX; [x]×[y]∉ψ; and ([x]×[x])∩([y]×[y])∉ψ.
Proof. The proof of the corollary can be easily deduced from Theorems 4.1, 4.3 and Definition 2.1.
Corollary 4.4. Let (X,ΘX,ψ) be a symmetric b-UFIL limit space, then the following statements are equivalent:
(i) X is ¯T0.
(ii) X is T1.
(iii) For all x,y∈X with x≠y, {x,y}∉ΘX; and [x]×[y]∉ψ.
Proof. The proof of the corollary can be easily deduced from Theorems 4.1, 4.3 and Definition 2.1.
Definition 4.3. (Set convergence) (cf. [32]) For an arbitrary set X, let ΘX⊂P(X) be a non-empty boundedness of X and q⊂ΘX×F(X). A pair (ΘX,q) is called a set-convergence on X and the triplet (X,ΘX,q) is known as a set-convergence space (or S-Conv space) if the following axioms hold:
(S-Conv1) E∈ΘX implies (E,[E])∈q;
(S-Conv2) (∅,ξ)∈q implies ξ=P(X);
(S-Conv3) (E,ξ)∈q and ξ⊂ξ′∈F(X) implies (E,ξ′)∈q.
A set-convergence space (X,ΘX,q) is called a reordered set-convergence space (or ROS-Conv space) provided that the following axiom holds:
(S-Conv4) If E∈ΘX and (E,ξ)∈q then for E′⊂E∈ΘX with E′≠∅ implies (E′,ξ)∈q.
Let (X,ΘX,q) and (Y,ΘY,p) be a pair of S-Conv spaces and h:X→Y be a map. Then h is called bounded continuous (or b-continuous) map if h is bounded and h transfers convergent filters.
We denote S-Conv (respectively ROS-Conv) as the category of S-Conv spaces (respectively reordered S-Conv spaces) and b-continuous maps. Also, we write ξqE for (E,ξ)∈q.
Note that if we restrict ΘX to be the discrete bounded structure on X, then many point-convergence spaces in the classical sense, such as, limit spaces, Kent-convergence spaces, topological spaces etc., can be embedded into ROS-Conv spaces. Also note that the category ROS-Conv can be regarded as a full subcategory of b-UFIL as mentioned in [32].
For a b-UFIL space (X,ΘX,μ), the corresponding ROS-Conv structure (ΘX,qμ) can be achieved provided that the following axioms hold:
(i) ξqμ∅ iff ξ=P(X);
(ii) ξqμE iff [E]×ξ∈μ, ∀E∈ΘX∖{∅}.
Definition 4.4. (cf. [32]) Let (X,ΘX,q) be a ROS-Conv space. A reordered set-convergence pair (ΘX,q) is said to be:
(1) T0 set- convergence iff the following condition holds, i.e.
(T0) ∀a,b∈X, [a]q{b} and [b]q{a} implies that a=b;
(2) T1 set- convergence iff the following condition holds, i.e.
(T1) ∀a,b∈X and [a]q{b} implies that a=b.
Remark 4.3. (cf. [32]) Let (X,ΘX,μ) be a b-UFIL space. The pair (ΘX,μ) of b-UFIL structure on X is said to be T0 (respectively T1) iff the corresponding pair (ΘX,qμ) is T0 (respectively T1) set- convergence. Note that we refer it as usual.
Corollary 4.5. Let (X,ΘX,ψ) be a discrete symmetric b-UFIL limit space, then the following statements are equivalent.
(i) X is ¯T0;
(ii) X is T1;
(iii) X is T0 (in the usual sense);
(iv) X is T1 (in the usual sense);
(v) For all x,y∈X with x≠y, [x]×[y]∉ψ.
Proof. It follows from Corollary 4.4, Remark 4.3 and Definition 2.2(ⅲ).
Corollary 4.6. The following categories are isomorphic.
(i) ¯T0DISb-UFIL;
(ii) ¯T0PUConv;
(iii) ¯T0BONb-UFIL.
Proof. It follows from Theorem 4.1, Corollary 4.1, Definition 2.1 and Theorem 3.1.10 of [30].
Corollary 4.7. The following categories are isomorphic.
(i) ¯T0DISsb-UFIL;
(ii) ¯T0SUConv;
(iii) T1SUConv;
(iv) ¯T0BONsb-UFIL;
(v) T1BONsb-UFIL.
Proof. It follows from Corollaries 4.1–4.3, Theorems 4.4 and 4.6 of [9].
Definition 5.1. (cf. [32]) Given a topological functor F:G→Set, and a full and isomorphism-closed subcategory H of G, we say that H is:
(1) Epireflective in G if and only if H is closed under the formation of products and extremal subobjects (i.e., subspaces).
(2) Quotient-reflective in G if and only if H is epireflective in G and closed under finer structures (i.e., if X∈H, Y∈G, F(X)=F(Y), and id:X→Y is a G-morphism, then Y∈H).
Theorem 5.1. (i) Every ¯T0b-UFIL (resp. T0b-UFIL, T1b-UFIL) is a quotient-reflective subcategory of b-UFIL.
(ii) T′0b-UFIL is a cartesian closed and hereditary topological construct.
Proof. (ⅰ) Let G=¯T0b-UFIL and (A,ΘA,μA)∈G. It can be easily verified that A is full subcategory, isomorphism-closed and closed under finer structures. We are left to show that it is also closed under extremal sub-objects and closed under the formation of products.
Let X⊂A and (ΘX,μX) be the sub-b-UFIL structure on X induced by i:X→A. We show that (X,ΘX,μX) is a ¯T0b-UFIL space. Suppose that {x,y}∈ΘX for any x,y∈X with x≠y. Then i({x,y})={i(x),i(y)}={x,y}∈ΘA, a contradiction by Theorem 4.1. Thus, {x,y}∉ΘX. Similarly, let [x]×[y]∈μX and ([x]×[x])∩([y]×[y])∈μX, then (i×i)([x]×[y])=[x]×[y]∈μA and (i×i)(([x]×[x])∩([y]×[y]))=([x]×[x])∩([y]×[y])∈μA, again a contradiction. Thus [x]×[y]∉μX and ([x]×[x])∩([y]×[y])∉μX. Hence, A is closed under extremal subobjects.
Next, suppose that A=∏j∈IAj, where (ΘAj,μAj) are the ¯T0b-UFIL structures on Aj induced by πj:A→Aj for all j∈I, i.e., (Aj,ΘAj,μAj)∈G. We show that (A,ΘA,μA) is a ¯T0b-UFIL space. Let {x,y}∈ΘA for any x,y∈A with x≠y. Then πj({x,y})={πj(x),πj(y)}={xj,yj}∈ΘAj, a contradiction to Theorem 4.1. Thus {x,y}∉ΘA. Similarly, suppose that [x]×[y]∈μA and ([x]×[x])∩([y]×[y])∈μA, then there exists j∈I for which xj≠yj∈Aj, such that (πj×πj)([x]×[y])=[xj]×[yj]∈μAj and (πj×πj)(([x]×[x])∩([y]×[y]))=([xj]×[xj])∩([yj]×[yj])∈μAj, a contradiction. Thus [x]×[y]∉μA and ([x]×[x])∩([y]×[y])∉μA. Hence, A is closed under the formation of products.
Therefore, the category ¯T0b-UFIL is a quotient-reflective subcategory of b-UFIL.
Analogous to the above argument, setting G=T0b-UFIL or T1b-UFIL, the proof can be easily deduced by using Theorem 4.2 or Theorem 4.3, respectively.
(ⅱ) By Theorem 4.4, both b-UFIL and T′0b-UFIL are isomorphic categories, and consequently, by Theorems 2.9.4 and 2.9.5 of [33], T′0b-UFIL is a cartesian closed and hereditary topological construct.
First of all, we characterized local ¯T0, local T′0 and local T1 b-UFIL spaces, and showed that every local T1 b-UFIL is local ¯T0 b-UFIL but converse is not true in general. Moreover, we characterized ¯T0, T′0, T0 and T1 in the category b-UFIL, and showed that T1 ⟹ ¯T0 ⟹ T0 ⟹ T′0, but the converse does not hold in general and provided some related results. Furthermore, we showed that under ¯T0 condition, ¯T0DISb-UFIL ≅ ¯T0PUConv ≅ ¯T0BONb-UFIL which is not isomorphic in general. Also, we showed the isomorphic relation among ¯T0DISsb-UFIL, ¯T0SUConv, T1SUConv, ¯T0BONsb-UFIL and T1BONsb-UFIL, and examined their relationships with the usual ones. Finally, we examined that ¯T0b-UFIL, T0b-UFIL and T1b-UFIL are quotient-reflective subcategories of b-UFIL, and T′0b-UFIL is a hereditary and cartesian closed topological category. In light of this study, the following can be examined in b-UFIL as a future research work:
(ⅰ) Can one characterize closed and strongly closed objects in b-UFIL, and what would be their corresponding closure operators using the notion of closedness in b-UFIL?
(ⅱ) How can one characterize irreducibility, soberness, connectedness and hyperconnectedness in the category b-UFIL? Can Urysohn Lemma and Tietze Extension Theorem be extended in the category of b-UFIL?
(ⅲ) How one can define pre-Hausdorff, Hausdorff, regular and normal objects in b-UFIL, and what would be their relation to the classical ones?
We declare that we have no conflicts of interest.
[1] | J. Adámek, H. Herrlich, G. E. Strecker, Abstract and concrete categories, New York: Wiley, 1990. |
[2] | M. Baran, Separation properties, Indian J. Pure Appl. Math., 23 (1991), 333–341. |
[3] | M. Baran, Generalized local separation properties, Indian J. Pure Appl. Math., 25 (1994), 615–620. |
[4] | M. Baran, H. Altındis, T0-objects in topological categories, J. Univ. Kuwait (Sci.), 22 (1995), 123–127. |
[5] | M. Baran, Separation properties in topological categories, Math. Balkanica, 10 (1996), 39–48. |
[6] |
M. Baran, Completely regular objects and normal objects in topological categories, Acta Math. Hung., 80 (1998), 211–224. https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1006550726143 doi: 10.1023/A:1006550726143
![]() |
[7] |
M. Baran, Compactness, perfectness, separation, minimality and closedness with respect to closure operators, Appl. Categor. Struct., 10 (2002), 403–415. https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1016388102703 doi: 10.1023/A:1016388102703
![]() |
[8] |
M. Baran, PreT2 objects in topological categories, Appl. Categor. Struct., 17 (2009), 591–602. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10485-008-9161-4 doi: 10.1007/s10485-008-9161-4
![]() |
[9] | M. Baran, S. Kula, A. Erciyes, T0 and T1 semiuniform convergence spaces, Filomat, 27 (2013), 537–546. |
[10] | M. Baran, S. Kula, T. M. Baran, M. Qasim, Closure operators in semiuniform convergence spaces, Filomat, 30 (2016), 131–140. |
[11] |
M. Baran, H. Abughalwa, Sober spaces, Turkish J. Math., 46 (2022), 299–310. https://doi.org/10.3906/mat-2109-95 doi: 10.3906/mat-2109-95
![]() |
[12] |
T. M. Baran, Closedness, separation and connectedness in pseudo-quasi-semi metric spaces, Filomat, 34 (2020), 4757–4766. https://doi.org/10.2298/FIL2014757B doi: 10.2298/FIL2014757B
![]() |
[13] |
T. M. Baran, A. Erciyes, T4, Urysohn's lemma and Tietze extension theorem for constant filter convergence spaces, Turkish J. Math., 45 (2021), 843–855. https://doi.org/10.3906/mat-2012-101 doi: 10.3906/mat-2012-101
![]() |
[14] |
T. M. Baran, M. Kula, Separation axioms, Urysohn's lemma and Tietze extension theorem for extended pseudo-quasi-semi metric spaces, Filomat, 36 (2022), 703–713. https://doi.org/10.2298/FIL2202703B doi: 10.2298/FIL2202703B
![]() |
[15] | G. C. L. Brümmer, A categorial study of initiality in uniform topology, University of Cape Town, 1971. |
[16] |
D. Dikranjan, E. Giuli, Closure operators Ⅰ, Topology Appl., 27 (1987), 129–143. https://doi.org/10.1016/0166-8641(87)90100-3 doi: 10.1016/0166-8641(87)90100-3
![]() |
[17] | D. B. Doitchinov, A unified theory of topological spaces, proximity spaces and uniform spaces, Soviet Math. Dokl., 5 (1964), 595–598. |
[18] | A. Erciyes, T. M. Baran, M. Qasim, Closure operators in constant filter convergence spaces, Konuralp J. Math., 8 (2020), 185–191. |
[19] | F. Peter, W. F. Lindgren, Quasi-uniform spaces, 1982. |
[20] |
J. M. Harvey, T0-separation in topological categories, Quaest. Math., 2 (1977), 177–190. https://doi.org/10.1080/16073606.1977.9632541 doi: 10.1080/16073606.1977.9632541
![]() |
[21] |
G. T. Herman, On topology as applied to image analysis, Comput. Vis. Graph. Image Process., 52 (1990), 409–415. https://doi.org/10.1016/0734-189X(90)90084-9 doi: 10.1016/0734-189X(90)90084-9
![]() |
[22] | H. Herrlich, Topological structures, Math. Centre Tracts, 52 (1974), 59–122. |
[23] | R. E. Hoffmann, (E,M)-universally topological functors, Habilitationsscheift, Universität Düsseldorf, 1974. |
[24] |
G. Janelidze, Light morphisms for generalized T0-reflections, Topology Appl., 156 (2009), 2109–2115. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.topol.2009.03.031 doi: 10.1016/j.topol.2009.03.031
![]() |
[25] | P. T. Johnstone, Stone spaces, New York: Academic Press, 1977. |
[26] | M. Katĕtov, On continuity structures and spaces of mappings, Comment. Math. Univ. Carolin., 6 (1965), 257–278. |
[27] | D. C. Kent, Convergence functions and their related topologies, Fund. Math., 54 (1964), 125–133. |
[28] |
V. A. Kovalevsky, Finite topology as applied to image analysis, Comput. Vis. Graph. Image Process., 46 (1989), 141–161. https://doi.org/10.1016/0734-189X(89)90165-5 doi: 10.1016/0734-189X(89)90165-5
![]() |
[29] |
V. Kovalevsky, R. Kopperman, Some topology-based image processing algorithms, Ann. New York Acad. Sci., 728 (1994), 174–182. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1749-6632.1994.tb44143.x doi: 10.1111/j.1749-6632.1994.tb44143.x
![]() |
[30] | S. Kula, Closedness and T0, T1 objects in the category of preuniform convergence spaces, Ph. D. thesis, Turkey: Erciyes University, 2014. |
[31] |
D. Leseberg, Z. Vaziry, The quasitopos of b-uniform filter spaces, Math. Appl., 7 (2018), 155–171. https://doi.org/10.13164/ma.2018.13 doi: 10.13164/ma.2018.13
![]() |
[32] |
D. Leseberg, Z. Vaziry, On the completeness of non-symmetrical uniform convergence with some links to approach spaces, Math. Appl., 8 (2019), 37–57. https://doi.org/10.13164/ma.2019.04 doi: 10.13164/ma.2019.04
![]() |
[33] | D. Leseberg, Z. Vaziry, Bounded topology, Lap Lambert Academic Publishing, 2019. |
[34] | T. Marny, Rechts-Bikategoriestrukturen in topologischen Kategorien: Inaugural-dissertation, 1973. |
[35] | G. Preuß, Semiuniform convergence spaces, Math. Japn., 41 (1995), 465–491. |
[36] | G. Preuss, Foundations of topology: An approach to convenient topology, Dordrecht: Springer Science & Business Media, 2002. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-0489-3 |
[37] |
M. Qasim, M. Baran, H. Abughalwa, Closure operators in convergence approach spaces, Turkish J. Math., 45 (2021), 139–152. https://doi.org/10.3906/mat-2008-65 doi: 10.3906/mat-2008-65
![]() |
[38] | A. Salibra, A continuum of theories of lambda calculus without semantics, In: Proceedings 16th Annual IEEE Symposium on Logic in Computer Science, 2001,334–343. https://doi.org/10.1109/LICS.2001.932509 |
[39] | J. E. Stoy, Denotational semantics: the Scott-Strachey approach to programming language theory, MIT Press, 1981. |
[40] |
S. Weck-Schwarz, T0-objects and separated objects in topological categories, Quaest. Math., 14 (1991), 315–325. https://doi.org/10.1080/16073606.1991.9631649 doi: 10.1080/16073606.1991.9631649
![]() |
1. | Muhammad Qasim, Arbaz Jehan Khan, Samirah Alsulami, Shoaib Assar, Some topological aspects of interval spaces, 2023, 8, 2473-6988, 3826, 10.3934/math.2023190 | |
2. | Sana Khadim, Muhammad Qasim, Closure operators and connectedness in bounded uniform filter spaces, 2022, 36, 0354-5180, 7027, 10.2298/FIL2220027K |