Research article Special Issues

Prejudice, privilege, and power: Conflicts and cooperation between recognizable groups

  • The problem of cooperation remains one of the fundamental questions in the fields of biology, sociology, and economics. The emergence and maintenance of cooperation are naturally affected by group dynamics, since individuals are likely to behave differently based on shared group membership. We here formulate a model of socio-economic power between two prejudiced groups, and explore the conditions for their cooperative coexistence under two social scenarios in a well-mixed environment. Each scenario corresponds to an asymmetrical increase in the payoffs for mutual cooperation in either cross-group or within-group interactions. In the 'inter-dependence' scenario payoffs of cross-group cooperation are enhanced, while in the 'group-cohesion' scenario payoffs of within-group cooperation are enhanced. We find that stable cooperative coexistence is possible only in the inter-dependence scenario. The conditions for such coexistence are highly sensitive to prejudice, defined as the reduction in probability for cross-group cooperation, and less sensitive to privilege, defined as the enhancements to payoffs of cross-group cooperation.

    Citation: Jeremy Bingham, Pietro Landi, Cang Hui. Prejudice, privilege, and power: Conflicts and cooperation between recognizable groups[J]. Mathematical Biosciences and Engineering, 2019, 16(5): 4092-4106. doi: 10.3934/mbe.2019203

    Related Papers:

    [1] Sharon M. Cameron, Ariel Cintrón-Arias . Prisoner's Dilemma on real social networks: Revisited. Mathematical Biosciences and Engineering, 2013, 10(5&6): 1381-1398. doi: 10.3934/mbe.2013.10.1381
    [2] Yifei Wang, Xinzhu Meng . Evolutionary game dynamics of cooperation in prisoner's dilemma with time delay. Mathematical Biosciences and Engineering, 2023, 20(3): 5024-5042. doi: 10.3934/mbe.2023233
    [3] Saheb Pal, Nikhil Pal, Sudip Samanta, Joydev Chattopadhyay . Fear effect in prey and hunting cooperation among predators in a Leslie-Gower model. Mathematical Biosciences and Engineering, 2019, 16(5): 5146-5179. doi: 10.3934/mbe.2019258
    [4] Zhiyan Xing, Yanlong Yang, Zuopeng Hu . Nash equilibrium realization of population games based on social learning processes. Mathematical Biosciences and Engineering, 2023, 20(9): 17116-17137. doi: 10.3934/mbe.2023763
    [5] Bo Lan, Lei Zhuang, Qin Zhou . An evolutionary game analysis of digital currency innovation and regulatory coordination. Mathematical Biosciences and Engineering, 2023, 20(5): 9018-9040. doi: 10.3934/mbe.2023396
    [6] Huan Zhao, Xi Chen . Study on knowledge cooperation of interdisciplinary research team based on evolutionary game theory. Mathematical Biosciences and Engineering, 2023, 20(5): 8782-8799. doi: 10.3934/mbe.2023386
    [7] Yuanyuan Huang, Yiping Hao, Min Wang, Wen Zhou, Zhijun Wu . Optimality and stability of symmetric evolutionary games with applications in genetic selection. Mathematical Biosciences and Engineering, 2015, 12(3): 503-523. doi: 10.3934/mbe.2015.12.503
    [8] José F. Fontanari . Cooperation in the face of crisis: effect of demographic noise in collective-risk social dilemmas. Mathematical Biosciences and Engineering, 2024, 21(11): 7480-7500. doi: 10.3934/mbe.2024329
    [9] Jialing Li, Guiju Zhu, Xinya Hu, Ruqian Fei, Dan Yu, Dong Wang . Study on the evolutionary strategy of upward patient transfer in the loose medical consortia. Mathematical Biosciences and Engineering, 2023, 20(9): 16846-16865. doi: 10.3934/mbe.2023751
    [10] Andrzej Swierniak, Michal Krzeslak . Application of evolutionary games to modeling carcinogenesis. Mathematical Biosciences and Engineering, 2013, 10(3): 873-911. doi: 10.3934/mbe.2013.10.873
  • The problem of cooperation remains one of the fundamental questions in the fields of biology, sociology, and economics. The emergence and maintenance of cooperation are naturally affected by group dynamics, since individuals are likely to behave differently based on shared group membership. We here formulate a model of socio-economic power between two prejudiced groups, and explore the conditions for their cooperative coexistence under two social scenarios in a well-mixed environment. Each scenario corresponds to an asymmetrical increase in the payoffs for mutual cooperation in either cross-group or within-group interactions. In the 'inter-dependence' scenario payoffs of cross-group cooperation are enhanced, while in the 'group-cohesion' scenario payoffs of within-group cooperation are enhanced. We find that stable cooperative coexistence is possible only in the inter-dependence scenario. The conditions for such coexistence are highly sensitive to prejudice, defined as the reduction in probability for cross-group cooperation, and less sensitive to privilege, defined as the enhancements to payoffs of cross-group cooperation.


    Cooperation can be found in many contexts and at many scales, both in nature and human societies, and can occur even between species [1,2]. Cooperation, defined as the giving up of individual reproductive success (fitness) to provide some fitness benefit to other individual(s), appears on the surface to be incompatible with Darwinian natural selection [3,4]. However, cooperative groups may have a higher average fitness than defective (or selfish) groups. Herein lies the paradox: how can cooperation, which once established is better for everyone, succeed in the face of individual incentive to defect?

    The emergence and fixation of cooperation has been explained through a number of mechanisms, including kin selection [5], reciprocity [6], reputation (indirect reciprocity) [7,8], cooperator recognition (green beards) [9], assortative encounter (direct or network-based)[10] and various forms of punishment [11,15,12,14], as well as more complex network effects [18,17,16].These mechanisms, though promoting cooperation, tend to foster higher levels of cooperation between members in the same local community, family group, or language group (in the case of indirect reciprocity). For example, network-based assortment allows clusters of cooperators to avoid contact with the rest of the population [19,20,21]. Indirect reciprocity works by letting players know each other's reputations; players choose whether to cooperate or defect based on whether the prospective player has cooperated or defected in previous interactions; reputation is more easily spread within members of the same language group. Direct reciprocity requires that players have a high probability of encountering one another again, while such repeated interactions are more likely within social groups. Kin selection allows levels of cooperation between individuals according to their relatedness [19]. Clearly, these mechanisms are not as effective at promoting cooperation between individuals which are genetically, spatially, or socially distant. Such mechanisms (or network configurations) are often associated with lower bounds on the benefit/cost ratio [19] for which cooperation can persist [22].

    Ever since the first diversification in life forms, the potential for conflict between different groups of individuals has been present. In systems with social structures or groupings, such as ant colonies or human societies, various degrees of cooperation and conflict occur. Consequently, groups are often separated by large distances or unsuitable terrains, so that conflict between groups can be intentionally or unintentionally reduced [23]. Unfortunately, this is not always the case.

    Humans are set apart in the sheer number of functional groups we form, such as companies, tribes and nations, and group divisions hold enormous influence in our everyday lives. Conflicts between groups have driven some of the most destructive patterns of human behavior, despite the fact that individuals within groups (who are in effect acting out the conflict) may not even want to support inter-group conflict [24]. Importantly, in most such cases, group membership is viscous but remains exchangeable (e.g. moving into another company or migrating to another country). In reality, the boundaries between groups can range from highly fluid (e.g. company employees) to nearly unbreachable (e.g. ethnic groups). Here we focus on the unbreachable end of this spectrum. While the contexts of inter-group conflicts vary, they share on the individual scale at least one common driver: people are more cooperative with members of their own groups. Studies in social psychology have shown that people are more trusting, more communicative, and less selfish when interacting with a member of a designated 'in-group' even when the group allocation is nothing more than a label given by experimenters [25]; these effects are stronger for pre-existing social identity groupings such as families, ethnic groups, and citizens of a country [26], and functional group identities such as corporate teams, school peer-groups, or neighborhood improvement organizations [27].

    A typical paradox of cooperation is the tragedy of the commons [28], in which a shared resource is vulnerable to over-use by unscrupulous individuals. This situation has been encoded mathematically in the form of the public goods game and its philosophically equivalent two-player game, the prisoner's dilemma [6]. While the prisoner's dilemma is a standard tool for explaining the evolution of cooperation, and represents the hardest problem to solve from a game theory perspective, empirical studies have suggested that many scenarios often characterized as prisoner's dilemmas may in fact be better classified as stag hunts, depending on the parameters involved [31,29,30]. The stag hunt represents a scenario where the players must cooperate to achieve a higher goal, such as hunting a stag, but may be assured of some lesser payoff if they choose to act alone, hunting hares instead [32]. A player in a stag hunt is better off 'defecting' (acting alone) if they expect that the other player will defect, but should cooperate if they expect that the other player will cooperate. The lack of consensus regarding which game best represents real social interactions is hardly surprising considering their enormous complexity. Our model lies somewhere between the camps of this dispute.

    Evolutionary game theory has looked at the problem of cooperation within and between recognizable groups (often referred to as 'groups with tags') through two broad lenses. One lens looks at the simultaneous evolution of group structure and cooperation [33,34,35], while the other looks at the evolutionary dynamics of identity, conflict and cooperation in the context of pre-existing groups [36,39,38,37]. Studies using spatial models have found that in the context of recognizable group divisions, ethnocentrism - cooperation within the group - dominates, followed by humanitarianism - cooperating regardless of group membership [33,40].

    The aim of this work is to develop a simple, tractable model of socio-economic power dynamics and cooperation in a system with two recognizable population groups. The generality of our model places it in an ideal position to be further developed in order to refine restrictive assumptions and address more specific scenarios. The rest of this paper is structured as follows. First, we describe the two social scenarios that we consider, each one a limiting case of certain real-life group dynamics. We then specify the rules governing the dynamics of the system, and analyze the resulting system of differential equations, focusing on conditions for cooperation and group coexistence.

    Our model describes the prevalence of cooperation within two distinct, recognizable groups and the relative socio-economic power of the two groups. People in the model ('players') engage in two-player games, in which each must choose whether to 'cooperate' (C) or 'defect' (D). Players can identify whether they are playing with a member of their own group ('within-group games') or the other group ('cross-group games'). We will focus on two scenarios concerning the difference between within-group and cross-group games.

    Payoffs in our model are in terms of socio-economic power, and group size represents the agammaegate socio-economic power of a group. 'Socio-economic power' may take the form of economic, social or cultural influence, and is used interchangeably with 'power'. These are connected in real societies by production and consumption of different sets of practical and artistic products. Our model assumes a ''well-mixed" population, in which encounter rates are determined by group-level socio-economic power and strategy prevalence in each group. In other words, the total socio-economic power of a group determines the rate at which players encounter players of that group.

    There is significant evidence to suggest that group membership is an important factor for establishing role-models, and within-group understanding facilitates the copying of successful strategies from fellow group members [41,24]. Following this line of reasoning, players in our model copy successful strategies that they observe being played by other members of their group. Group identities are distinguished by fixed, recognizable characteristics, so that players do not (rather, are unable to) switch groups. Groups shift in relative power due to payoffs, but this does not directly affect the prevalence of cooperators in either group.

    In the 'group cohesion' scenario, the payoffs for mutual cooperation within a group are enhanced (see Table 1). This reflects the evidence that members of the same group are able to communicate more effectively with one another and trust each other more [25]. Many real-life groups have institutions (formal or social) which support initiatives of the group, punish defectors in the group (thus lowering the effective benefit of defection) or support victims of defection from within the group (thus lowering effective cost of cooperation when the other player defects). We incorporate these into a net enhancement of the payoffs for mutual cooperation within the group, though the magnitude can differ between groups.

    Table 1.  Payoffs for a player of group i choosing the row strategy in cross-group games (left) and within-group games (right), where αi>1 is the cohesiveness of group i, and b>c>0. Notice that when αi>bbc the within-group game becomes a stag hunt for group i.

     | Show Table
    DownLoad: CSV

    Almost every real system has at least some of these properties. This scenario is particularly well-suited to systems in which different groups speak different languages and/or have very different cultural norms, and in which social support is provided primarily by fellow group members. We summarize these effects in a parameter αi>1 we call 'cohesiveness' (see Table 1). Note that cooperators need not act the same way with co-players from a different group and in general cooperate less in cross-group games due to prejudice (see sub-section 2.3).

    In the 'inter-dependence' scenario, the payoffs of cross-group cooperation are enhanced (see Table 2). This reflects the fact that in many situations with two groups, each group has something uniquely valuable to offer, though the enhancement to cooperation may not be the same for both groups. This manifests itself in traditional family dynamics (with complementary though unequal roles for men and women), as well as the current trends of inter-disciplinary research teams and multi-cultural offices of leading technology companies. Studies on group identity have shown that people tend to punish defecting members of their own group less, leading to a higher relative payoff of defection [42,24]. These are just a few examples of factors that would contribute to increased payoffs for cross-group cooperation. A group's αi-value in the inter-dependence scenario is referred to as the group's 'privilege'.

    Table 2.  Payoffs for a player of group i choosing the row strategy in cross-group games (left) and within-group games (right), where αi>1 is the privilege of group i and b>c>0. Notice that when αi>bbc the cross-group game becomes a stag hunt for group i.

     | Show Table
    DownLoad: CSV

    The regions of applicability of the two scenarios are of course not entirely disjoint. We analyze them separately to get a better understanding of the dynamics implied by each. In either case, the enhanced cooperation can shift the within-group or cross-group interactions from a prisoner's dilemma, where defection is always favored, to a stag hunt.

    Each group consists of 'cooperators' and 'defectors'. Cooperators always cooperate in within-group games and cooperate in cross-group games with probability 0<βi1 (for group i). We refer at times to β-values (trust), but also to prejudice levels =1βi. Defectors always defect. The strategy-update rule is as follows. Players compare their expected payoffs from a single round to the average payoffs of other players in their group. If the average payoff of other players is larger, they update their strategy with a probability proportional to the difference in payoffs between themselves and the average payoff, otherwise they keep playing the same strategy. The rate of change in frequency of strategists* in each group under the strategy update rule is given by the replicator equations[10,43]:

    *For the sake of simplicity we describe the within-group dynamics as strategy dynamics, but based on our rule for encounter rates the within-group dynamics could also describe pure power dynamics with no strategy update, or a mixture of strategy update and power dynamics.

    ˙n1C=n1C(P1C¯P1) (2.1)
    ˙n1D=n1D(P1D¯P1) (2.2)
    ˙n2C=n2C(P2C¯P2) (2.3)
    ˙n2D=n2D(P2D¯P2), (2.4)

    where niS represents the frequency of players in group i playing strategy S in within-group games, while PiS denotes the expected payoff of those players (e.g. P2D is the expected payoff of group 2 defectors). Note that the frequencies above are within each group, so that n1C+n1D=n2C+n2D=1. The expected payoffs of each group are given by ¯P1=n1CP1C+n1DP1D and ¯P2=n2CP2C+n2DP2D [22]. Changes in socio-economic power are governed by the replicator equations:

    ˙n1=n1(¯P1ˉP) (2.5)
    ˙n2=n2(¯P2ˉP), (2.6)

    where n1 and n2 denote the share (or prevalence) of socio-economic power wielded by group 1 and group 2 respectively; n1+n2=1, and we set ˉP=n1¯P1+n2¯P2. Notice that the distribution of socio-economic power ni (due to its effect on encounter rates) as well as the levels of cooperation in either group determine the expected payoffs at both the strategy (PiS) and actually also at the population (¯Pi) level (see next section).

    Note that the definition of the state variables as relative frequencies (and the corresponding form of the replicator equations) allow us to define the system using just three equations and three variables. The state of the system can be specified by a three-tuple (n1C,n2C,n1) and the dynamics of the system are defined by Eqs 2.1, 2.3 and 2.5.

    The results of a preliminary analysis in which we assume a separation of timescales between strategy-update dynamics (Eqs 2.1, 2.3) and group-power dynamics (Eq 2.5) are displayed in Table 3 (see Appendix for details).

    Table 3.  Summary of conditions for cooperation and coexistence. The first two rows show results when we assume separate timescales for strategy (Eqs 2.1, 2.3) and group dynamics (Eq 2.5), while the third row shows results for the full system. Note that there exist equivalent requirements, symmetric with respect to group indices, which for the sake of brevity we have not listed here. The condition without group indices (third row second column) is derived for groups with equal prejudice and privilege (β1=β2=β and α1=α2=α).
    Group Cohesion Scenario Inter-dependence Scenario
    Strategy Dynamics (cooperation) n1(α11)β1n2+n1α1b>c (α11)β1β2n2n1+β2(1+β1)n2b>c
    Group Dynamics (Coexistence) α2β2α2β1b<c β1β2(α21)(1β1)β1β2(α21)(1β2)b>c
    Cooperation and Coexistence Not attainable α>1+1ββ2 and (α1)β21+β+β2(α1)b>c

     | Show Table
    DownLoad: CSV

    We focus here on the three dimensional 'full system', with no separation of timescales. We solve the system of replicator equations to find fixed points of the system. We analyze the stability of the fixed points analytically where possible. In the non-symmetric case (α1α2 and/or β1β2), this is not possible for all fixed points, so we explore the system numerically. Notice that by model construction if both groups are fully defective the distinction between the two groups becomes irrelevant (i.e. there is a line of trivial attractors, see Figures 1, 2).

    Figure 1.  Representative trajectories of the symmetric group cohesion scenario, with α1=α2=5, β1=β2=0.7, b=2, c=0.5. Blue dots and thick lines represent stable fixed points, green diamonds represent saddle points and crosses represent unstable fixed points.
    Figure 2.  Fixed points and their stability for various parameter settings in the inter-dependence scenario. Blue dot and thick lines represent stable fixed points, green diamonds represent saddle points and crosses mark unstable fixed points. b=3 and c=1.

    Based on the payoff structure for the group cohesion scenario, in which the payoffs for within-group cooperation are enhanced (Table 1), we calculate the expected payoffs of group 1 cooperators, group 1 defectors, group 2 cooperators and group 2 defectors:

    The expected payoffs for defectors are the same in both scenarios so are not repeated in the next section.

    P1C=n1(n1Cα1(bc)+n1D(c))+n2(n2C(β1β2(bc)+β1(1β2)(c)+(1β1)β2b)+n2Dβ1(c)) (3.1)
    P1D=n1n1Cb+n2n2Cβ2b (3.2)
    P2C=n2(n2Cα2(bc)+n2D(c))+n1(n1C(β1β2(bc)+β1(1β2)b+(1β1)β2(c))+n1Dβ2(c)) (3.3)
    P2D=n2n2Cb+n1n1Cβ1b. (3.4)

    Each term in the expected payoffs represents the probability of a certain type of encounter, multiplied by its payoff for the subject player. For example, the n2n2Cβ1β2(bc) term in P1C is the probability that a given group 1 cooperator will encounter a group 2 cooperator (n2n2C) multiplied by the probability that both players cooperate (β1β2), multiplied by the payoff for the group 1 cooperator when both players cooperate (bc). The αi values appear in the terms corresponding to within-group cooperation.

    We then substitute these values into the replicator Eqs 2.1, 2.3 and 2.5. We find the fixed points of the system by setting Eqs 2.1, 2.3, 2.5 to zero and solving for n1C, n2C and n1. We use the Jacobian eigenvalues and eigenvectors to classify the local stability of each fixed point.

    There are 19 analytic solutions to the resulting system of equations. Of these solutions, two correspond to a negative share of power for one group and are discarded. 11 of the 17 realistic solutions do not correspond to the extinction (complete loss of socio-economic power) of one of the groups.

    We find that cooperation with group coexistence is not possible. The cooperation and coexistence equilibrium is a saddle point, while the only two non-trivial attractors of the system occur when there is one group dominating and cooperating, and one group extinct and defecting. In symmetric games, while high levels of group cohesion (α) allow one group to become cooperative, it is inevitably at the expense of eliminating the other group. More prejudiced groups (small β-values) are more likely to dominate. Initial advantage, however, moves each group's threshold of cooperation according to the ratio of the other group's initial power to its own, while an increase in prejudice (decrease in β) corresponds to a linear decrease of the cooperation threshold.

    We continue our exploration by examining a few particular cases. In all cases we set b=2 and c=0.5. We begin with a group-symmetric model, setting α1=α2, β1=β2. The initially more powerful group dominates, after which the losing group moves gradually towards defection (Figure 1). We then break the symmetry of the system to examine the context in which one group has strong within-group cohesiveness and high levels of prejudice, but the results do not differ qualitatively from those of the symmetric case; the basin of attraction for dominance of a group increases as it gets relatively stronger and more prejudiced (high αi and low βi). Thus, in the group cohesion scenario, only one group will dominate and cooperate, while the other will lose all of its power and defect.

    We now examine the scenario in which cooperation between groups has enhanced payoffs, while within-group game has the payoff structure of the standard prisoner's dilemma (Table 2). Following the same procedure, we calculate the expected payoffs of group 1 cooperators and group 2 cooperators:

    Payoffs for defectors are still given by Eqs 3.2 and 3.4

    P1C=n1(n1C(bc)+n1D(c))+n2(n2C(β1β2α1(bc)+β1(1β2)(c)+(1β1)β2b)+n2Dβ1(c))P2C=n2(n2C(bc)+n2D(c))+n1(n1C(β1β2α2(bc)+β1(1β2)b+(1β1)β2(c))+n1Dβ2(c)),

    and substitute these values into the replicator Eqs 2.1, 2.3 and 2.5.

    The system has 15 fixed points, two of which correspond to negative group power. Seven fixed points correspond to extinction of one group. Interestingly, none of these are asymptotically stable. There are fixed points where one group cooperates while the other defects and goes extinct, but the inter-dependence means that the cooperation of the dominating group is not stable. The defection of the extinct group is unstable if (for group 2 defecting and extinct) β1(α21)(bc)>c. This and its group-symmetric equivalent (obtained by swapping group indices) are in fact the conditions for the stability of cooperation (or instability of defection) of the extinct group at all the extinction fixed points. The fact that dominant groups have unstable cooperation while extinct groups may have stable cooperation agrees qualitatively with existing results using density-dependent replicator dynamics [4,22].

    Fixed points where one group cooperates while the other defects, but both coexist, enter the system when both βi<bcb. These points are however always unstable in at least one direction. Stability would require, for example, that bcβ2b<β1cβ1β2(α11)(bc), which cannot be satisfied with allowed parameter values while the point is in the positive unit cube.

    A full-cooperation fixed point occurs at

    n1=b(β21)c(β11)+β1β2(bc)(α11)(bc)(β1+β22+β1β2(α1+α22)).

    When the system is symmetrical (α1=α2=α and β1=β2=β) the full-cooperation fixed point is stable if (bc)(β+αβ2β21)<0 and c(1+β)β2(bc)(α1)<0. Together these lead to the conditions: α>1+1ββ2 for stability in strategy dynamics and α>1+c(1+β)(bc)β2 for stability in group power dynamics. The second condition is usually harder to reach, but for large (bc) and high β it may be achieved with lower α. The stability of cooperative coexistence depends approximately hyperbolically on prejudice (1β).

    Unfortunately the analytic forms of the eigenvalues of the full-cooperation fixed point are prohibitively complicated in the non-symmetrical case, but a scan of parameter space assures us that the full-cooperation fixed point can remain stable with non-symmetric parameter values, provided αi and βi values are large enough; stability of full-cooperation is much more sensitive to βi values, as in the separated-timescales analysis (Figure 2).

    We modeled the shifts of socio-economic power in a system with two recognizable groups interacting with prejudice. We considered two scenarios: in the group cohesion scenario players received increased payoffs for within-group cooperation, while in the inter-dependence scenario players received increased payoffs for cooperating with members of the other group.

    As might be expected, our analysis suggests very different results for the two scenarios. The results for the group cohesion scenario paint a grim picture: while high levels of group cohesion (α) allow one group to become cooperative, it is inevitably at the expense of eliminating the other group. More prejudiced groups (small β-values) are more likely to dominate. Initial advantage, however, moves each group's threshold of cooperation according to the ratio of the other group's initial power to its own, while an increase in prejudice (decrease in trust β) corresponds to a linear decrease of the cooperation threshold.

    The inter-dependence scenario allows stable coexistence of the two groups, but is highly sensitive to prejudice. Even relatively small increases in prejudice (decreases in trust β) may necessitate large increases in privilege (α) in order to maintain stable coexistence. Provided prejudice is controlled, stable coexistence can be maintained even with high privilege difference (e.g. α1>>α2). Hence we observe that in the context of our model, for cooperative coexistence, prejudice plays a stronger role than privilege.

    Our work provides a number of suggestions for successful reconciliation and reduction of inequality. Two results stand out: the first is that members of opposite groups should have some incentive to cooperate with one another, and cross-group cooperation must be highly productive, particularly when mutual trust is low (prejudice levels are high). The second is that even moderate levels of prejudice necessitate large incentives, while low levels of prejudice allow cooperation even with modest incentives and inequality.

    Organizations working to foster cross-group cooperation should note that that initiatives to increase trust (reduce prejudice) may be needed in order to make a difference; prejudice reduction in high-prejudice contexts is likely to be much more cost effective than direct subsidy of cross-group cooperation. If for example a government were to consider subsidizing multi-group businesses, our model would suggest that this would be effective only when prejudice levels are already reasonably low.

    In multi-ethnic societies, affirmative action is sometimes enacted to facilitate economic upliftment of underprivileged groups through integration into sectors of the economy mostly dominated by privileged groups [44]. This in the context of our model can be thought of as incentivizing cross-group cooperation. Despite its significant successes, the practical implementation of affirmative action has come under criticism for its narrow scope of impact and for perpetuating racialist dynamics [44,46,45]. Our model would suggest that affirmative action cannot efficiently drive broad social transformation while prejudice levels remain high, and while different ethnic groups are unable to effectively communicate (necessary for productive cross-group cooperation). In this regard our model agrees qualitatively with other theorists who have suggested that improving mutual language literacy between groups would increase the possibilities for productive cross-group cooperation, and thus move the society toward higher levels of cooperative coexistence [47,48]. These interpretations should not be taken as scientific comments on social issues, but rather as food for thought and inspiration for deeper investigations.

    Our model differs from other models of dynamics between recognizable groups in a number of ways. Firstly we assume two discrete recognizable groups, rather than continuous traits [40,49]. The heterogeneity within groups is limited to strategy choice, so we do not address issues of adoption or rejection of group identity within groups (eg self-racialisation and assimilation in [36] or ethnocentric vs humanitarian in [50]). Thirdly, in our model the two groups exist a priori, and players do not change groups (Eqs 2.1–2.4).

    Of particular interest to this work is the theory of green beards (so dubbed by Dawkins [51]), which explores the potential for cooperation to emerge amongst bearers of a recognizable set of genes. Bearers of green beard genes (green beards) have a tendency to treat other green beards differently from non-green beards, for example by cooperating only with fellow green beards and thus reducing their chances of cooperating with a defector (see [52,53]).

    The model proposed in this paper is intentionally simple, paving the way for a number of natural extensions, many of which could be combined. Assortative encounter could increase the amount of within-group interactions, or could increase the probability that cooperators encounter other cooperators (the usual assumption), with a stronger effect for within-group encounters. The second obvious step would be to include changing prejudice, for example using adaptive dynamics [54], and to relate this to the group-level assortment (more prejudiced people avoid the other group). Real processes are constantly co-evolving, and this type of thinking could be incorporated into many aspects of the model and extensions (see [55] for a recent review).

    The effect of population size could be incorporated; while models involving finite populations and stochasticity are more realistic they preclude certain useful analyses and converge to infinite-population models under a range of assumptions [19]. Density-dependent selection, as opposed to frequency dependent selection, may be a more relevant modification to the population structure of our model, where the size of the economy along with opportunities for economic, social and artistic innovation and development take the place of the carrying capacity in traditional ecological models [4,22]. Another layer of realism could be captured by incorporating different payoffs for strategy update than for power transfer, allowing for the inclusion of perception of benefit based on group membership.

    These extensions - some of which would implicitly emerge - could then be studied in the context of networks of interacting agents, opening new and interesting avenues for research [56]. Networks naturally support the incorporation of complex and varied strategy-update rules [16], variability in the individual tendencies to separately assimilate and reproduce social norms [57], and form a natural bridge to methods of statistical physics [17]. A significant step towards reality is made with the consideration of complex self-forming social network structures [58]: the list of phenomena which might emerge is near-endless, particularly with complex individual rules for the development of the network [16]. As well as providing extraordinary flexibility, evolutionary game theory on networks has displayed a variety of realistic features including criticality [59], spatial chaos [60], self-organized punishment and rewarding, and territorial competition [17]. Most extensions would however mean sacrificing the analytic tractability of results.

    We suggest that those interested in empirical work related to this model look to social media and other online interaction spaces - news site comment sections, forums, etc. - for data. Automated data collection (web crawlers) could be used along with classification techniques to identify sentiments and group membership within such environments - for example the comments, likes, views and endorsements of beauty bloggers on youtube - and observe the progression of these behaviors. Government surveys could also provide valuable data for analysis with a more economic emphasis. A number of experimental methods for the calibration and evaluation of cooperation models have recently been proposed, including accessible and scalable online alternatives to traditional experiments [61,62,63].

    We described a socio-economic system of two recognizable groups in two hypothetical scenarios. In the group cohesion scenario, people benefit most from cooperating within their group, while in the inter-dependence scenario cross-group cooperation is more productive. We found that in the group cohesion scenario, one group always dominates the other. In the inter-dependence scenario the groups can both cooperate, even with high inequality, but only if they have low prejudice levels.

    The relevance of cooperation between groups is clear in many societies worldwide. Models such as ours may yield insights into the complex dynamics that govern the course of society, and should be developed with the aim of overcoming the barriers inherent to coexistence of multiple groups.

    Our findings suggest that, while equitable distribution of the benefits from cooperative behavior plays an important role, organizations working towards improving inter-group relations should focus first on increasing group inter-dependence and reducing prejudice.

    The authors are grateful to the editorial team for the opportunity to contribute to this special issue, and to the four anonymous reviewers for sharing their time and expertise. P.L. and C.H. acknowledge support from the National Research Foundation (NRF) of South Africa (grant nos. 89967, 109244 and 109683). J.B. acknowledges support from the National Research Foundation (NRF) of South Africa, the African Institute for Mathematical Sciences (AIMS) South Africa and the Southern African Center for Epidemiological Modeling and Analysis (SACEMA).

    All authors declare no conflicts of interest in this paper.



    [1] T. Clutton-Brock, Cooperation between non-kin in animal societies, Nature, 462 (2009), 51–57.
    [2] R. L. Trivers, The evolution of reciprocal altruism, Q. Rev. Biol., 46 (1971), 35–57.
    [3] C. Darwin, On the origin of species by means of natural selection, or preservation of favoured races in the struggle for life. John Murray, London, 1859.
    [4] C. Hauert, M. Holmes and M. Doebeli, Evolutionary games and population dynamics: maintenance of cooperation in public goods games, Proc. R. Soc. B, 273 (2006), 2565–2570.
    [5] W. D. Hamilton, The genetical ecolution of social behavior I and II, J. Theor. Biol., 7 (1964), 1–52.
    [6] R. Axelrod, The Evolution of Cooperation, Basic Books, Inc., New York, 1981.
    [7] R. Boyd and P. J. Richerson, The evolution of indirect reciprocity, Social Networks, 11 (1989), 213 – 236.
    [8] M. A. Nowak and K. Sigmund, Evolution of indirect reciprocity, Nature, 437 (2005), 1291–1298.
    [9] A. Gardner and S. A. West, Greenbeards, Evolution, 64 (2009), 25–38.
    [10] S. D. Carroll, Evolutionary games and population dynamics, Q. Rev. Biol., 74 (1999), 347–347.
    [11] R. Boyd and P. J. Richerson, Culture and the evolution of human cooperation, Philos. Trans. R. Soc. B, 364 (2009), 3281–3288.
    [12] L. Liu, S. Wang, X. Chen, et al., Evolutionary dynamics in the public goods games with switching between punishment and exclusion, Chaos, 28 (2018), 103105.
    [13] X. Chen, T. Sasaki and M. Perc, Evolution of public cooperation in a monitored society with implicated punishment and within-group enforcement, Sci. Rep., 5 (2011).
    [14] M. Perc, J. Gomez-Gardenes, A. Szolnoki, et al., Evolutionary dymanics of group interactions on structured populations: a review, J. R. Soc. Interface, 10 (2013), 20120997.
    [15] A. Szolnoki and M. Perc, Second-order free-riding on antisocial punishment restores the effectiveness of prosocial punishment, Phys. Rev. X, 7 (2017), 198192.
    [16] K. Mahmoodi, B. J. West and P. Grigolini, Self-organizing Complex Networks: individual versus global rules, Front. Physiol., 8 (2017), 478.
    [17] M. Perc, J. J. Jordan, D. G. Rand, et al., Statistical physics of human cooperation Phys. Rep., 687 (2017), 1–51.
    [18] Z. Wang, L. Wang, A. Szolnoki, et al., Evolutionary games on multilayer networks: a colloquium,Eur. Phys. J. B, 88 (2015), 124.
    [19] M. A. Nowak, Five rules for the evolution of cooperation., Science, 314 (2006), 1560–1563.
    [20] K. M. Page and M. A. Nowak, Unifying evolutionary dynamics, J. Theor. Biol., 219 (2002), 93–98.
    [21] M. van Baalend and D. A. Rand The unit of selection in viscous populations and the evolution of altruism, J. Theor. Biol., 193 (1998), 631–648.
    [22] F. Zhang and C. Hui, Eco-evolutionary feedback and the invasion of cooperation in prisoner's dilemma games, PLoS One, 6 (2011), e27523.
    [23] F. Zhang, Y. Tao, Z. Li, et al., The evolution of cooperation on fragmented landscapes: the spatial hamilton rule, Evol. Ecol. Res., 12 (2010), 23–33.
    [24] P. Richerson, A .V. Bell, and R. Baldini et al., Cultural group selection plays an essential role in explaining human cooperation: A sketch of the evidence, Behav. Brain Sci., 29 (2016), 30.
    [25] B. C. Eaton, M. Eswaran and R. J. Oxoby, 'Us' and 'Them': The origin of identity, and its economic implications, Can. J. Econ., 44 (2011), 719–748.
    [26] R. M. Kramer and M. B. Brewer, Effects of group identity on resource use in a simulated commons dilemma, J. Pers. Soc. Psychol., 46 (1984), 1044–1057.
    [27] M. B. Brewer and R. M. Kramer, Choice behavior in social dilemmas: Effects of social identity, group size, and decision framing, J. Pers. Soc. Psychol., 50 (1986), 543–549.
    [28] G. Hardin, The trajedy of the commons, Science, 162 (1968), 1243–1248.
    [29] D. H. Cole and P. Z. Grossman, Institutions matter! why the herder problem is not a prisoner's dilemma, Theo. Dec., 69 (2008), 219–231.
    [30] R. H. McAdams, Beyond the prisoners' dilemma: Coordination, game theory, and law, South. Calif. Law Rev., 82 (2009), 209.
    [31] B. Skyrms, The Stag Hunt and the Evolution of Social Structure, Cambridge University Press, 2003.
    [32] J.-J. Rousseau, R. D. Masters and C. Kelly, Discourse on the origins of inequality; polemics; and, political economy. Hanover, NH, Published for Dartmouth College by University Press of New England, 1992.
    [33] T. Antal, H. Ohtsuki, J. Wakeley, et al., Evolution of cooperation by phenotypic similarity, Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA, 106 (2009), 8597–8600.
    [34] F. Fu, C. E. Tarnita, N. A. Christakis, et al., Evolution of in-group favoritism, Sci. Rep., 2 (2012), 460.
    [35] F. Jansson, What games support the evolution of an ingroup bias?, J. Theor. Biol., 373 (2015), 100–110.
    [36] W. A. Darity Jr, P. L. Mason and J. B. Stewart, The economics of identity: The origin and persistence of racial identity norms, J. Econ. Behav. Organ., 60 (2006), 283–305.
    [37] F. M. Kai and A. Konrad, Evolutionarily stable in-group favoritism and out-group spite in intergroup conflict, J. Theor. Biol., 306 (2012), 61–67.
    [38] N. Masuda, Ingroup favoritism and intergroup cooperation under indirect reciprocity based on group reputation, J. Theor. Biol., 311 (2012), 8–18.
    [39] K. Pattni, M. Broom and J. Rychtář, Evolutionary dynamics and the evolution of multiplayer cooperation in a subdivided population, J. Theor. Biol., 429 (2017), 105–115.
    [40] R. L. Riolo, M. D. Cohen and R. Axelrod, Evolution of cooperation without reciprocity, Nature,414 (2001), 441–443.
    [41] J. P. Bruner, Diversity and cooperation, Ph.D thesis, UC Irvine, 2014.
    [42] S. T. Powers, D. J. Taylor and J. J. Bryson, Punishment can promote defection in group-structured populations, J. Theor. Biol., 311 (2012), 107–116.
    [43] C. Hui, P. Landi, H. O. Minoarivelo, et al., Ecological and Evolutionary Modelling, Springer International Publishing, 2018.
    [44] N. Alexander, Affirmative action and the perpetuation of racial identities in post-apartheid South Africa, Edited version of a Lecture originally delivered at the East London Campus, University of Fort Hare, 2006.
    [45] K. Durrheim, M. Xoliswa and L. Brown, Race trouble: race, identity and inequality in post- apartheid South Africa, Lexington Books, 2011.
    [46] R. A. Wilson, The politics of truth and reconciliation in South Africa: Legitimizing the post- apartheid state, Cambridge University Press, 2001.
    [47] N. Alexander, Language policy and national unity in South Africa/Azania, Buchu Books, Cape Town, 1989.
    [48] N. W. Thiong'o, Decolonizing the mind: the politics of language in African literature, James Currey, London, 1986.
    [49] P. Landi and F. Dercole, The social diversification of fashion, J. Math. Soc., 40 (2016), 185–205.
    [50] M. Hartshorn, A. Kaznatcheev and T. Schultz, The evolutionary dominance of ethnocentric cooperation, J. Artif. Soc. S., 16 (2013), 7.
    [51] R. Dawkins, The Selfish Gene, Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK, 1976.
    [52] V. A. A. Jansen and M. van Baalen, Altruism through beard chromodynamics, Nature, 440 (2006), 663.
    [53] A. Traulsen and M. A. Nowak, Chromodynamics of cooperation in finite populations, PLoS One,2 (2007), e270.
    [54] C. Hui, H. O. Minoarivelo and P. Landi, Modelling coevolution in ecological networks with adaptive dynamics, Math. Method. Appl. Sci., 41 (2018), 8407–8422.
    [55] M. Perc and A. Szolnoki Coevolutionary games - a mini review, BioSystems, 99 (2010), 109–125.
    [56] V. Capraro and M. Perc, Grand challenges in social physics: in pursuit of moral behavior, Front. Phys., 6 (2018), 107.
    [57] K. Mahmoodi, P. Grigolini and B. J. West, On social sensitivity to either zealot or independent minorities, Chaos, Soliton. Fract., 110 (2018), 185–190.
    [58] P. Landi and C. Piccardi, Community analysis in directed networks: in-, out- and pseudocommunities, Phys. Rev. E, 89 (2014), 012814.
    [59] K. Mahmoodi and P. Grigolini Evolutionary game theory and criticality J. Phys. A- Math. Theor., 50 (2017), 015101.
    [60] M.A.NowakandR.M.May, Evolutionarygamesandspatialchaos, Nature, 359(1992), 826–829.v 61. J. J. Horton, D. G. Rand and R. J. Zeckhauser, The online laboratory: conducting experiments in a real labor market. Exp. Econ., 14 (2011), 399–425.
    [61] 62. A. Ofra and D. G. Rand, Economic games on the internet: the effect of $1 stakes, PloS One, 7 (2012), e314
    [62] 63. D. G. Rand, The promise of Mechanical Turk: how online labor markets can help theorists run behavioural experiments, J. Theor. Biol., 299 (2012), 172–179.
  • Reader Comments
  • © 2019 the Author(s), licensee AIMS Press. This is an open access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0)
通讯作者: 陈斌, bchen63@163.com
  • 1. 

    沈阳化工大学材料科学与工程学院 沈阳 110142

  1. 本站搜索
  2. 百度学术搜索
  3. 万方数据库搜索
  4. CNKI搜索

Metrics

Article views(4746) PDF downloads(754) Cited by(0)

Other Articles By Authors

/

DownLoad:  Full-Size Img  PowerPoint
Return
Return

Catalog